3
The Linguistics of Argumentation

There is a great diversity of argumentative texts, among which are news editorials, judicial deliberations, blog posts and radio or TV debates. Texts may originate from oral transcriptions, with limitations on the oral features (see Chapter 9). An argumentative text is generally organized around a main claim and possibly a set of secondary claims. When the text is long or complex, it may include several main claims found in different text sections, which may be related or not. This is the case, for example, in political debates where different topics may be addressed. Statements for or against these claims are developed in the text. These statements may also appear in various types of discourses that are not argumentative, for example in texts that are factual or that develop an explanation on a given topic. It is their relation with a claim that gives them their argumentative orientation.

Given a text, the problem is then to be able (1) to identify if it is argumentative and, if so, (2) to identify claims, hierarchies of claims, and their related supports and attacks. All supports or attacks do not have the same importance: they are more or less strong and central with respect to a claim. Secondary or peripheral statements with respect to a claim are probably less useful than the most central ones. The overall argumentative organization of a text is called an argumentation.

It is not easy to identify arguments and the structure of an argumentation in a text. First, most arguments are not stated as clearly as Toulmin’s model suggests it. This model is in fact not frequently used in corpus analysis of arguments. Next, domain or general purpose knowledge is often necessary to identify claims and their related justifications. Finally, claims can have very diverse language forms with more or less typical linguistic cues.

In argument mining, supports or attacks of a given claim are generally searched in a variety of texts that are related to that claim. For example, concerning opinions on political decisions or product properties, attacks and supports are found in, for example, blogs, news editorials, specialized journals or consumer opinion platforms. Mining such attacks and supports spread over several sources is even more difficult than mining them in a single text where reference problems and lexical variations are less important.

From a conceptual point of view, a claim is a proposition that is credible and plausible, but not a proposition that can be shown to be true. It must always be possible to argue against a claim, i.e. to support its opposite. Next, a statement interpreted as a justification must be related to a precise claim. Justifications do not exist without any corresponding claim. Arguments, composed of a claim and of one or more justifications, are speech acts of a pragmatic nature.

Natural language has a strong expressive capability: it allows speakers to formulate an idea in a large variety of ways, including the use of metaphors, implicit references, allusions or indirect discourse. Natural language is a powerful means of developing an argumentation, but identifying arguments is a very challenging task for annotators. Then it is not surprising that annotator disagreements are high and that automatically identifying arguments is very challenging (see Chapter 6).

In this chapter, dedicated to the linguistic dimensions of argumentation, section 3.1 addresses the linguistic structure of claims, then section 3.2 deals with the linguistic structure of supports and attacks. Claims, supports and attacks share a large number of linguistic cues and constructions. Then, section 3.3 addresses the analysis of the strength of a statement based on language cues. This analysis includes the taking into account of discourse structures and of the argument scheme that has been used. This chapter ends with a presentation of the various facets of rhetoric, which are important in argumentation.

3.1. The structure of claims

Claims may have a large diversity of forms: a fact, a thesis, an opinion, a judgment, a position on a topic, a question, a rhetorical question, etc. Claims must have a debatable character: they express something that is plausible but may be questioned in various ways. This plausible character is often realized by means of evaluative terms or expressions. Statements become claims when it is possible to find related justifications or attacks. This section presents the main linguistic cues that are typical of claims. However, a number of claims are not marked by any linguistic cues: their argumentative character is pragmatic. Furthermore, some of these linguistic cues can also be found in justifications and other types of pragmatic constructions, which makes the identification of claims difficult.

The first difficult point in claim identification is to delimit the text span that could constitute a claim. In general, it is a sentence, ending with a full stop, an exclamation or a question mark. A claim may be longer if it includes restrictions, comments, definitions or circumstances of various kinds. A sentence may also be composed of several claims, possibly hierarchically organized, for example:

Due to the necessity of a systematic vaccination against Ebola, the authorities of country C have decided to reduce the funding of education in English.

This statement contains two potential claims (systematic vaccination and funding reduction), which can be equally debated. Furthermore, the causal link between the two can be also debated. If the vaccination necessity is attacked, then the latter claim is also attacked. The need to delimit claims has led to the emergence of a research topic, as well as the notion of argumentative discourse unit (ADU), derived from the notion of elementary discourse unit (EDU) in discourse analysis. ADUs are segments that, in general, contain an argument, a claim, a support or an attack.

Claim delimitation is addressed in Chapter 6, which is dedicated to argument annotation. So far, it is essentially an experimental process based on annotations, even if cues such as punctuation, connectors and relative clauses can be taken into account.

The second challenge is to identify statements that have a debatable character. This identification can be realized partly by analyzing the linguistic elements in the statement, which introduce this debatable character. A first set of linguistic cues are those that are proper to the content of the claim. These cues include, but are not limited to, the following:

– Scalar adjectives such as easy, difficult, efficient, unsafe, which have an evaluative dimension in the context of a claim. These adjectives evaluate a property or a characteristic that is central to concepts of the claim or of closely related concepts. For example, in:

Vaccine development is very expensive, the adjuvant is toxic,

expensive evaluates the property “cost” of the vaccine, which has the general properties of artifacts such as costs and functions. In the second claim, where adjuvant is a derived concept, which refers to a part of the vaccine that is injected, “toxic” refers to a more indirect property of medicines, for example, their “side effects”. Evaluative adjectives can also appear in comparative expressions:

electricity produced from nuclear energy is cheaper than electricity produced from coal or wind.

Nuclear wastes are more dangerous than coal wastes.

Boolean adjectives are less frequent since they tend to express a position that is more definitive: Ebola vaccination must be compulsory...

  • – Verbs that have a clear positive or negative polarity, e.g. to protect, to prevent, to damage. This polarity introduces a flexible character that easily suggests discussions and debates.
  • – Adverbs that focus on specific features such as necessity, obligation and possibility such as necessarily and inevitably where these features can be debated. Adverbs associated with the notions of frequency or completion are also frequent in claims since the level of frequency they induce can be debated, e.g. generally, almost never, seldom, rarely.
  • – Modals and modal expressions that convey an idea of possibility or plausibility such as

might, should, would, could be and should be possible; the vaccine against Ebola should be compulsory in infected areas.

In Romance languages, conditional and subjunctive modes are also used to convey plausibility.

  • – Forms such as why should that typically introduce rhetorical questions:

Why should citizens save money? To support SMEs.

In this example, the debatable segment is the response provided by the utterer.

  • – Typical types of punctuations such as exclamation marks:

Let our committee make a decision!

Such a statement, if not ironic, could be followed by evaluations of various kinds on the committee’s ability to make decisions.

Based on the notion of evaluative expression given above, the following constructions are typical of simple claims:

  1. 1) If the main verb of the claim has a clear positive or negative polarity (e.g. to protect, to prevent, to pollute), then language realizations of a claim include:
    1. (1a) a proposition with this verb,
    2. (1b) the negation of the verb or verb phrase (VP),
    3. (1c) the use of adverbs of frequency, completion, etc., possibly combined with a negation: in general, almost never, seldom, rarely, not frequently, very frequently, fully, systematically, or
    4. (1d) the use of modals expressing doubt or uncertainty: seem, could, should.

For example:

Vaccination prevents Ebola dissemination.

Vaccination does not prevent any disease dissemination.

In general, vaccination should prevent disease dissemination.

2) If the evaluative expression applies to the head noun of the claim, in general, the subject, then language realizations involve attribute structures with one or more adjectives with a clear polarity in the context at stake that evaluate the concept: toxic, useless, expensive or their negative forms. These can be modified by intensifiers such as: 100%, totally. These intensifiers can also generate by themselves a debatable character proper to claims. The main verb is often neutral such as to be or a light verb. For example, in:

Women’s rights are not totally respected in this part of the world.

“not totally respected” applied to the noun “rights” introduces potential controversies.

Control constructions, where head verbs subcategorize for a proposition or a sentential complement, may transform a statement into a claim by introducing some form of uncertainty. These control constructions may also appear in supports or attacks. In both cases, their scope is the claim or the entire argument. As far as claims are concerned, control constructions can be organized according to the following linguistic categories:

– Propositional attitude verbs and expressions that express a position. In this class, verbs are included and expressions such as:

think, believe, I am convinced that.

The semantics of these verbs is investigated in depth in [WIE 87]. Propositional attitude constructions can be modified by a negation or by a modal such as would, could, have to as in: I would think that, I have to believe that.

– Psychological expressions or expressions denoting a position or an experience. They include verbs and expressions such as:

I feel, I am worried about, I am intrigued by, dream of, be encouraged by, tend to.

These terms are often in an initial position with respect to the statement they introduce, or in a final position for constructions such as worries me as in:

the obligation of vaccination worries me,

where the nominalized sentence is raised to be the main focus of the sentence, it then becomes the grammatical subject.

– Performative verbs, which partly overlap with the other classes presented here. They clearly introduce the idea of a thesis or of a position that could be attacked. Verbs in this category are, for example, pretend, support, recommend, assume and claim. Their corresponding nominal expressions are, for example, my position, thesis and recommendation is. These cues explicitly indicate that the statement they subcategorize is a claim.

– Report verbs and associated constructions. They introduce claims in a direct manner or as a reported speech from, for example, other participants in a debate or from external persons, frequently considered as experts. Similarly to the above categories, these constructions can be modified by a negation or a modal. In this category, we include verbs and expressions such as report, say, mention, state, announce, discuss and claim and their morphological variants. For some of these verbs, it is not straightforward to transform a factual statement into a claim since they do not lend themselves easily to controversies, this is the case for report, say, announce and declare, which are rather neutral and need additional linguistic cues. Conversely, terms such as claim, affirm, maintain and allege are much more typical of claims and easily induce debates. The first utterance below is not as typical of a claim as the second one, in spite of the evaluative “dangerous”:

A doctor said that Ebola is a dangerous disease.

A doctor claimed that Ebola is a dangerous disease.

– Epistemic verbs and constructions. These also occur quite frequently. They include expressions such as:

know, my understanding is that, I am convinced that, I suppose, I realize, it is reasonable to assume, infer, imply, I can see, it is reasonable to, this can mean, this may mean.

These mainly introduce doubts while others are clear positive statements.

– Modal expressions. These are left-adjuncts to a proposition that modify some of the expressions described above. Most of them either weaken the statement or introduce a hypothesis:

it should be possible, it is probable that.

For example, the following claim and its justification:

it should be possible to have a systematic vaccination that creates sanitary belts to avoid the proliferation of the disease.

lend themselves to debates and controversies.

– Adverbials related to the expression of opinion. They indicate the strength of a claim but also its debatable character. They include:

probably, necessarily, most definitely, definitely, surely, usually, frequently, often, certainly, obviously, generally speaking, of course, indeed.

Finally, given a statement that is factual, a number of discourse structures adjoined to that fact may introduce a debatable character such as illustrations. It is not possible to develop in this section a systematic analysis of these discourse structures, however, a few relevant examples can be outlined to show the importance of this phenomenon.

Illustrations often take the form of an enumeration of elements to serve as examples. As a result, illustrations introduce some plausibility for supports or attacks because the elements in the enumeration can be used as starting points for these supports or attacks. For example:

the Ebola vaccine is easy to use for emerging countries (cheap, can be transported without any need for refrigeration, active for a long time).

Even if the main claim is consensual, some of the elements of the enumeration can be subject to debates, in particular when they contain fuzzy lexical items or expressions, such as for a long time. The term “cheap” could also be discussed.

Claims that include a purpose or goal may be subject to debates not on the main content of the claim but on its purpose. In:

Vaccination against Ebola is necessary to avoid any disease proliferation in territories close to those where Ebola is present.

the purpose can be debated in particular on the forms and speed of proliferation. Here, the purpose plays the role of a justification of the main claim. It can be attacked without really questioning the necessity of the vaccination, because it is not a very relevant justification or because it is rather weak. Similarly, the following purpose may weaken a factual statement:

[purpose in order to avoid any form of panic or, worse, of bio-terrorism], the authorities of Guinea closed their borders.

For example, the permeability of the border can be outlined and discussed.

3.2. The linguistics of justifications

Identifying justifications to a claim is also very challenging both from a linguistic and conceptual point of view, in particular when justifications are not adjacent to the claim. In this section, we consider justifications to a claim C (supports) as well as justifications to its negation ¬C, which are attacks of C.

The first difficulty is to relate a potential justification to a claim. A justification may support a facet of a claim instead of the whole claim. The terms used in a justification may require inferences and knowledge to relate it to a claim because the linguistic, conceptual and referential links to that issue are rarely direct and explicit. This is one of the main challenges of argument mining. Justifications are often evaluative natural language statements that become justifications because of the specific relations they have with another evaluative statement considered as a claim. Besides their evaluative dimensions, justifications may be causally related to a claim.

Let us illustrate the need for knowledge and inference when relating a claim and one of its justifications with the following example:

Claim: The situation of women has improved in India,

Statement found in another text: (a) early in the morning, we now see long lines of happy young girls with school bags walking along the roads.

(a) is a justification (support) of the claim, but it requires knowledge and inferences to make explicit, and possibly explain, the relationships between women’s conditions and young girls carrying school bags. Here, the relationship is education. Let us now consider:

(b) School buses must be provided so that schoolchildren do not reach the school totally exhausted after a long early morning walk.

(b) is an attack of (a), indeed: these young girls may not be so happy to be walking in the early morning, but it is not an attack of the claim: the facet that is concerned in the relation between (b) and (a) does not concern women’s conditions in particular.

So far, the relatedness problem has not been addressed in depth in argument mining, although it is crucial to identify arguments. In Chapter 4, we develop a few examples that show the complexity of the problem, which is a major limitation to the development of argument mining technology.

The next difficulty is identifying that the statement that is related to a given claim is a justification. The term justification must be considered in a broad sense: a justification adds content that contributes to the acceptability of a claim. It makes the claim more plausible, but it does not prove that it is true. For example, a statement that is a reformulation or an elaboration of a claim is not a justification, since the content that is added simply makes the claim clearer or more precise. An illustration can be considered as a justification in some contexts:

Claim: Vaccination against Ebola is dangerous,

illustration: One person died after an injection in Monrovia and two patients got sick in Guinea last week.

The illustration does not really justify why the vaccination is dangerous, it however adds strength to the claim.

When a justification is adjacent to a claim or adjacent to a referential expression associated with that claim, it may be linked to that claim by means of different types of connectors, among which:

  • – causal connectors such as because, since, as, so that, due to, resulting in
  • – purpose connectors and expressions such as to, in order to, so as to, to avoid, to prevent can also be used to introduce supports as well as attacks,
  • – connectors and expressions describing a result may also introduce a justification, for example: thus, therefore, as a consequence, hence, as a result,
  • – illustrations may play the role of justifications: they are introduced by typical terms such as: for example, e.g., for instance, such as, like, including,
  • – weak or strong forms of attacks can be characterized by concessive connectors such as: although, though, even if, despite, in spite of, however, nonetheless, nevertheless, or by
  • – contrast connectors such as: while, whereas, but, in contrast of, yet, instead of, rather, unlike.

More details can be found in [ANS 83] where a large number of connectors with an argumentative orientation are presented and illustrated for French. An equivalent set can be developed for English. This investigation considers that argumentation is essentially a linguistic and language act rather than a discursive action. Claim–justification pairs are investigated from the perspective of their possible sequences in language.

Let us come back to justifications. Since they support claims, justifications are also evaluative expressions. Similarly, attacks support the negation of the claim at stake. They use some of the linguistic categories presented above for claims, in particular scalar adjectives, adverbs, verbs with a positive or negative polarity, report verbs, epistemic constructions and adverbials. The class of propositional attitude verbs is extended to take into account verbs that denote forms of acceptance of rejection such as:

agree, deny, argue, refute, acknowledge, reckon, disagree, accept, reject,

possibly combined with modals such as would, negation or temporal or frequency adverbs: I always disagree with...

3.3. Evaluating the strength of claims, justifications and arguments

In an argument it is of much interest to evaluate the strength of a claim and the strength of a support or an attack separately. Strong claims call in general for stronger forms of supports or attacks than claims of a moderate strength. Therefore, the strength of a claim or of a support or an attack can be evaluated separately. Then the evaluation of a support or of an attack must be tuned with respect to the a priori strength of the claim to determine the overall strength of an argument.

We view the strength of a claim, a justification or an argument as a kind of metrics, which is essentially induced by linguistic factors, even if an accurate measure of the strength of a number of linguistic cues is domain dependent and difficult to evaluate. It follows that persuasion is a more pragmatic measure of strength where personal and contextual factors play an important role. These factors include readers’ or listeners’ profiles and expectations as well as their global cultural environment. In this chapter, strength is viewed as a linguistic phenomenon. However, strength may also be determined by other factors such as images, gestures, mimics and intonation in interactive situations (see Chapter 9).

There are several ways to measure the strength of arguments. Strength can be measured from a logical and pragmatic perspective or it can be measured from a linguistic point of view. Both approaches are not necessarily coherent but they must be combined to produce a relatively accurate measure of strength. Argument strength may be measured for each argument in isolation or for groups of related arguments, taking into account their relations and structure.

Investigations on argument strength share some aspects with the evaluation of strength in opinion analysis. This latter area is well developed and a number of resources are freely available. We do not go into it in this book. However, the notion of strength in argument mining is more complex since it involves a number of specific features, including the impact of argument schemes.

So far, investigations on argument strength have focused on a few aspects such as (1) teaching how to organize written essays and how to organize arguments and give them an appropriate strength, (2) research on persuasion which is, in our view, an analysis of strength in contexts (the domain and the audience of the argumentation are taken into account) and (3) in theoretical analysis of argumentation where graphs of attacks and supports are developed. Let us note for example [GRA 11] that deals with an in-depth analysis of persuasion and [ZHA 11] which investigates the content of persuasive messages. Sensitivity to argument strength of various populations is developed in [COR 04]. The impact of strength in conjunction with rhetorical questions has been addressed in [MUN 88]. A number of linguistic factors are analyzed in [ANS 83], and later in [EEM 01] and [EEM 92]. The notion of strength is an important element in opinion analysis, for example, to measure whether a specific feature in a product is appreciated or not, and to what extent. A number of resources has been developed to evaluate strength, in general out of context. Let us note the Stanford Sentiment Treebank (https://nlp.stanford.edu/sentiment/treebank.html). This resource is a well-developed and stable resource frequently used in opinion analysis. However, to the best of our knowledge, little has been done to characterize argument strength from a linguistic point of view and from the perspective of argument mining.

This section is organized as follows. In the first section, the contribution of individual lexical items found in propositions Pi is investigated. The hypothesis is that such propositions have an intrinsic strength independently of any claim. Next, we introduce structures from lexical semantics that enable the organization of the linguistic data. Then, the strength variations induced by the combination of several lexical items in a proposition and the support construction in which it may be embedded are explored and tested experimentally. Since it turns out that contextual effects in their broad sense are crucial to have an accurate estimate of the strength of an argument, several contextual parameters are discussed, in particular the impact of the discourse structures that are adjoined to a statement and the kind of argument scheme on which the argument relies.

3.3.1. Strength factors within a proposition

Similarly to the results obtained in opinion analysis, evaluating strength entailed by linguistic cues in argument expression is quite subjective. Two levels of the expression of strength are considered here: (1) the intrinsic strength conveyed by head terms used in propositions Pi and (2) the strength conveyed by expressions, such as propositional attitudes expressions, of which Pi is the sentential complement. The propositions Pi considered in this investigation have a simple syntactic structure. They are composed of a main point called the kernel and adjuncts – usually discourse structures – which add restrictions, justifications, purposes or illustrations to the kernel. These discourse structures may scope either over the proposition or over the entire argument.

There are many elements that may have an impact on the strength of a proposition Pi. Those with a higher impact are head elements such as verbs but also elements that are less prominent in the syntax such as evaluative adjectives and adverbs. The latter are analyzed as modifiers to the noun for adjectives and to the VP or to the sentence for adverbs. These linguistic elements are used to determine the orientation of the propositions Pi with respect to the claim (support, attack, possibly neutral). In addition, their implicit semantics is an important factor to evaluate the overall strength of an argument.

A number of categories of lexical items are developed below, some are shared with opinion analysis or sentiment analysis while others are more specific to argument analysis.

The main categories of elements internal to a proposition Pi that contribute to strength expression are as follows:

1) Positively oriented verbs, such as:

improve, benefit, optimize, reinforce, preserve, strengthen, guarantee, consolidate.

e.g. vaccination against Ebola is necessary because it guarantees the non-proliferation of the disease.

There are many such verbs. Their exact semantic contribution to strength and their orientation may depend on domains.

2) Negatively oriented verbs, such as:

affect, alter, break, demolish, hurt, lessen, ruin, undermine, damage.

For example, the claim:

the situation of women in India has improved,

is attacked by the proposition:

the persistent lack of education largely undermines their independence.

3) Similarly to verbs, a number of adjectives and adjectival compounds contribute to the orientation of an argument and the expression of strength. These are usually found in propositions where the verb is neutral (auxiliary, light verb, verbs such as allow, enable, where the orientation of the object is crucial) or where the verb is largely underspecified with respect to polarity and strength. Adjectives in this category are, for example:

useful, capable, consistent, resistant, compliant, beneficial, optimal

for the positively oriented ones and:

risky, polluted, dangerous, weak, harmful

for the negatively oriented ones. A typical example is:

vaccination against Ebola is dangerous because the adjuvant is toxic,

where toxic induces the orientation and the strength.

4) Expressions derived from verbs, past participles and adjectival compounds with a scalar dimension such as:

disappointing, potentially risky.

For example, a negatively oriented argument in relation with a standpoint on the necessity of nuclear plants is:

Pipe corrosion in nuclear plants is potentially risky.

5) Nouns that appear as subjects or objects in the proposition that have a positive or negative orientation, e.g. risk, disease, reward and success.

The expression of strength is also mediated by a number of terms, which introduce supports or attacks. These are called control constructions. These are composed of head verbs that subcategorize for a proposition or a sentential complement. Their scope is therefore the entire argument.

Control constructions can be organized according to several linguistic categories, which have been presented in the above sections. They include propositional attitude verbs, psychological expressions, report verbs, some epistemic constructions and modal expressions. They also include adverbs and adverb phrases denoting strength, frequency or probability, for example, probably, necessarily, most definitely, definitely, surely, usually, frequently, often, certainly, of course, obviously, generally speaking, of course and indeed.

3.3.2. Structuring expressions of strength by semantic category

It is obviously impossible to a priori assign strength values to the lexical items and expressions of the different categories given above, nor is it possible to assign weights to their combinations. An option is to structure these terms along scales, as for scalar adjectives in opinion analysis. In various experiments, it turns out that the polarity of about 75% of the adjectives is stable over domains. While the adjectives used in opinion expression lend themselves relatively easily to an evaluation of their positive or negative character, this is more complex for verbs, modals or the expressions given above. To organize the elements in the different categories, an experiment is made using non-branching proportional series [CRU 86], which allow to define partial orders over groups of terms with respect to a given measurable property. These scales organize terms of a category from those with a strong negative orientation to those with a strong positive orientation. A neutral point is mentioned: it is either a lexical term when such a term exists or an abstract point. The partial order introduces some flexibility by allowing several terms to be at a given point on the scale when it is not relevant or easy to make strength distinctions between them.

For example, the negatively and positively oriented verbs can be structured as follows:

[[ruin] - [break, demolish] - [hurt, alter, lessen, undermine, damage] - [affect] - Neutral - [preserve, guarantee] - [benefit] - [improve, consolidate, strengthen] - [optimize]].

Terms that are considered to have almost the same strength appear in the same set, represented between square brackets. The neutral point is represented by the constant “Neutral”, the two sets just before and after it have a moderate strength while the extremes sets are the strongest ones.

Adjectives are more difficult to structure because they do not modify the same property in a homogeneous way; for example, resistant and optimal do not operate on the same concepts, where optimal is rather of higher order. A scale that represents a kind of “safety” dimension can be developed as follows:


[[dangerous, harmful] - [risky, polluted] - [unsafe] - Neutral - [useful, beneficial] - [safe] - [certified]].

In this example, a certain number of adjectives are in the same set since these have a relatively similar impact on strength.

Finally, here is a scale for propositional attitude verbs:

[[deny - refute - reject] - [disagree] - Neutral - [believe, think, accept] - [agree, acknowledge, reckon] - [argue]].

The verbs to the extreme sides of the scale are more crucial in the acceptance or rejection of the claim than those close to the neutral point. Adverbials modify these verbs or the corresponding VP by adding or reducing the strength. These can be classified as follows by increasing levels of strength:

[[probably] - [indeed, usually, of course] - [often, frequently, generally speaking] - [definitely, surely, obviously, necessarily] - [most definitely]].

This approach can be extended to other categories of terms, which play a role in strength expression.

3.3.3. A simple representation of strength when combining several factors

It is frequent to have supports or attacks that include several terms expressing strength. For example, given the claim:

Nuclear plants are useful since they pollute less than coal or oil.

a proposition such as:

I am definitely convinced that nuclear plants should be banished.

includes the strong negative term banished in its statement, which is somewhat softened by the modal should. This proposition is included into an epistemic construction with a strong connotation: a strong verb convinced modified by the intensifier adverb definitely. Evaluating the strength of such a proposition compared to:

I am convinced that nuclear plants must be banished.

is not trivial, even for human experts.

To have an accurate analysis of the strength of propositions, a semantic representation of the elements that contribute to strength expression can be developed and interpreted via an interpretation model, which is largely experimental. This model is based on the categories of the elements found in the proposition and on a rough estimate of their strength, as reflected by the non-branching proportional series presented in section 3.3.2. For example, the proposition:

Nuclear plants should be banished.

has the following semantic representation with respect to its strength:

[argument verb(strong negative) ∧ modal(weaken)] where head terms have an attribute that represents their strength and modals or adverbials include an attribute that describes their function on the term they modify. In this example, banished is among the strongest negative verbs on the corresponding scale while the modal should weakens the strength of this verb. Next, the more complex proposition:

I am definitely convinced that nuclear plants should be banished,

which includes an epistemic construction, is represented as follows:

[control verb(epistemic, strong positive) ∧ adverbial(reinforce)]([argument verb(strong negative) ∧ modal(weaken)]).

Let us call this expression the signature of the strength of the proposition. Considering the different elements of this representation, the resulting strength is strong with a negative orientation. It would however be necessary to develop more accurate models based on readers’ real perception of strength, possibly via learning methods from specific annotations.

3.3.4. Pragmatic factors of strength expression

Several other factors, which are essentially contextual, have a major influence on the strength of supports or attacks, and on arguments more generally. Their influence is however difficult to accurately analyze.

The first factor is the discourse structures that may be adjoined to a proposition or to an argument. They mainly develop circumstances, conditions, restrictions and elaborations. The second factor is the argument scheme that has been used. Some are more commonly admitted or closer to deduction and are therefore stronger than others. The third factor is the context of the proposition interpreted as a support or an attack: it may be uttered in isolation or it may be part of a series of propositions. As developed in [EEM 92], propositions associated with a claim may be structured by series or in parallel. In the first case, the strength is the strength of the weakest one, and in the second case it is the strength of the strongest one. The fourth factor is the syntactic structure of the premise–conclusion pair where focus shifts can be observed via left extraposition. The last factor is the linguistic context of the utterance. For example, some debates may only use soft arguments in order to remain polite and to avoid strong attacks, whereas others use extremely strong terms even for arguments that are not crucial. In this section, the impact on argument strength of the first two factors is discussed. The remaining ones require additional investigations.

3.3.4.1. Influence of discourse structures on argument strength

Arguments are quite frequently associated with elements such as comments, elaborations, comparisons and illustrations, which can be considered as either forms of explanation or secondary or subordinated arguments. Some examples are developed in section 3.1 of this chapter. Let us consider here more complex cases, frequently encountered in argumentation related to opinion analysis. The discourse analysis provided here has been carried out with the discourse analysis platform TextCoop [SAI 12] (see also section 7.3.9).

The role of illustrations with respect to argument strength may be complex. Given the claim:

I do not recommend this hotel,

and a proposition such as:

The bathrooms were in bad condition: [ILLUSTRATION the showers leaked, and the plug mechanism in the bath jammed ...],

the illustrations given to support the diagnosis (“bad condition”’) do not seem to reinforce or weaken its strength. These are interpreted as reformulations, which is another way to say something without altering the initial content.

Let us consider other types of discourse relations such as the circumstance and justification relations. For example, possibly with a form of irony, the strength and polarity of “breakfast is excellent” is largely affected – if not reversed – by the contrast:

The breakfast is excellent,

[PRECISION with very imaginative exotic fruit salads]

[CONTRAST but most of the products are not fresh and most have passed their sell-by date].

More complex – yet realistic – arguments associated with restrictions of various sorts make the identification of the overall strength of an argument and of its various components quite challenging:

[CONTEXT We stayed here for a one day conference off-season], and the hotel was OK [CONCESSION - although the room I had was kind of weird.]

I think it was the sitting room to the suite on the top floor

[PRECISION - the bed was a fold-out bed, not comfortable, [CONCESSION (slept okay though)], and the coffee table was small, dirty and pushed to the side.]

[CONCESSION It did have a lovely terrace though] - shame it was raining cats and dogs.

[RECOMMENDATION Not a great experience.]

Depending on customers’ preferences, this opinion can be judged to be slightly positive or negative, in spite of the negative polarity of the recommendation, which turns out to be the main claim. Therefore, this opinion may either support or attack the claim I do not recommend this hotel.

Evaluating the impact of discourse structures is therefore a very challenging task. Even if the polarity and strength of each individual structure can be evaluated, their combination with the main argument and their interactions when there are several structures is complex and highly domain dependent.

3.3.4.2. The impact of argument schemes on argument strength

Another component that has an impact on strength is the inner structure of an argument and the underlying scheme that has been used. [WAL 08, WAL 15a, PAR 08] have identified and structured a large number of schemes which are used in everyday argumentation. Some of them can be detected via a linguistic analysis [FEN 11, GRE 17]. These can provide information on the strength of arguments. A number of schemes among the most frequently encountered are reviewed in this section; they complement the schemes presented in section 2.5.2.

– Argument from analogy

The typical form of arguments from analogy is as follows:

Premise 1: Generally, case C1 is similar to case C2.

Premise 2: A is true (false) in case C1.

Conclusion: A is true (false) in case C2.

For example:

It has been shown that vaccinating against malaria can be useless in some cases; similarly, the vaccine against Ebola is not recommended.

This sentence makes an analogy between two serious diseases and tries to show that if the vaccine against one of these diseases is useless, then the vaccine against the other is useless too. Some linguistic cues marking analogy are: similarly, x is like y, doing x is as [adjective useful, dangerous, crucial] as doing y.

– Argument from expert opinion

The typical structure of arguments from expert opinion is:

Premise 1: E is a reliable authority in the domain S.

Premise 2: A is a proposition contained in S.

Premise 3: E asserts that A.

Conclusion: Therefore, A.

An example of argument from expert opinion is:

Depression and anxiety should be taken seriously. The London School of Economy reports that half of all illnesses in the under 65s is mental.

Arguments from expert opinion are marked by two linguistic cues; first, nouns that identify the expert by his title or his function (e.g. expert, doctor, economist and politician); second, constructions such as reported speech that allow to indicate the expert’s opinion (e.g. claim, warn, explain and indicate). The strength of report verbs must be taken into account in the scheme. The opinion of experts is used in many cases to support a claim since it is hard to contradict an expertise. As a result, arguments from expert opinion have a strong impact.

Argument from negative consequences

This scheme has the following form:

Premise 1: If an action leads to bad consequences, all else being equal, it should not be brought about.

Premise 2: If action A is brought about, bad consequences will occur.

Conclusion: Therefore, A should not be brought about.

For example:

Vaccinating people against Ebola has reduced their immune system. This vaccine must not be used anymore.

is an argument from negative consequences.

Negative adjectives, nouns or verbs are usually found in the premise(s) (here, reduce), while action verbs used in the negative form are used in the conclusion (here, must not be used). Warning against negative consequences can have a strong impact, but the nouns and adjectives used can help determining how strong the argument is.

Arguments from examples

This scheme has the following form:

Premise 1: Example 1 is an example that supports claim P.

Premise 2: Example n is an example that supports claim P.

Conclusion: Claim P is true.

An illustration is:

It has been shown that the vaccine is not the right solution. For example, two weeks after the injection, an old man died and the fetus of a pregnant woman showed malformations.

Linguistic cues typical of illustration such as for example, for instance, in the same manner can contribute to detect arguments from example. Evaluating how the strength induced by this scheme interacts with the strength induced by the other argument schemes presented above requires some experimentation. It is not clear, for example, if they all operate at the same level, or if some have a higher weight. The strength of the argument based on examples can be measured from the number of examples used. The above argument has two premises (two examples) supporting the claim. The conclusion could be supported by many other examples of people who reacted badly to the vaccine, which would reinforce the claim that the vaccine is not the right solution.

Arguments from position to know

This scheme has the following form:

Premise 1: Source a is in a position to know about things in a certain subject domain S containing proposition A.

Premise 2: a asserts that A (in Domain S) is true (false).

Conclusion: A is true (false).

An illustration is:

A British politician visiting Western Africa has revealed that the number of deaths due to Ebola has dropped since the vaccination began. Vaccinating populations must therefore continue.

In this example, the claim that vaccinating against Ebola must continue is supported by the opinion of a British political figure. This type of argument is close to arguments from expert opinion. However, arguments from position to know are weaker than arguments from expert opinion because it is easier to question whether the person is able to have a clear and well-established opinion on that topic.

  • – Argument from popular opinion

Arguments from popular opinion take the following form:

Premise 1: Everybody is doing X.

Premise 2: X is a good thing to do.

Conclusions: Therefore, X must be the right thing to do.

An illustration is:

vaccination in general is a cheap and efficient way to get rid of major diseases, therefore all populations exposed to Ebola must systematically undergo vaccination.

Linguistic cues referring to populations and groups of people can help detect arguments from popular opinion (e.g. the population, people, individuals, everyone and all the persons). Similarly to arguments from position to know, arguments from popular opinion have less strength than the ones from expert opinion since the actions or opinions of groups of people can be discussed.

Arguments from cause to effect

This scheme has the following form:

Premise 1: Doing X will cause Y to occur or If X occurs then Y will occur,

Premise 2: X is done or X occurs,

Conclusion: Y will occur.

The statement:

A new vaccine has been developed, which will lower the number of deaths. Fewer farmers in the vaccinated area will die after its injection.

is an example of argument from cause to effect. This type of argument can be seen as an anticipation. Anticipation has, however, little credibility in many cases and, as a result, arguments from cause to effect are in general weak arguments.

Organizing schemes with respect to their strength

From the observations above, and as an illustration, a tentative classification of argument strength induced by argument schemes can be made. No domain knowledge is considered in this classification:

Strong: analogy, expert opinion

Moderate: negative consequences, from examples

Weak: position to know, popular opinion, cause to effect.

In [WAL 08], each scheme is associated with a number of critical questions that allow testing the soundness of the argument; these can be used in particular to attack the argument. For instance, the argument from analogy has the following critical questions:

  • – Are there respects in which C1 and C2 are different that would tend to undermine the force of the similarity cited?
  • – Is A the right conclusion to be drawn in C1?
  • – Is there some other case C3 that is also similar to C1, but in which some conclusion other than A could be drawn?

Additional examples of critical questions are provided in Chapter 2.

Evaluating the overall strength of critical questions per scheme can be used to determine the strength of the scheme with respect to an argument. An argument that has stronger critical questions could be a weak argument (it can be easily attacked), or, on the contrary, it can be a strong one (it is difficult to defeat it) if it does not raise so many critical questions.

Finally, the problem of fallacious arguments can interfere with strength evaluation. For example, analogy is sometimes classified as fallacious. Evaluating fallacious arguments is a major concern in argumentation, however, in practical situations, this means considering domain and general purpose knowledge and inferences that are beyond the current state of the art of argument mining.

3.4. Rhetoric and argumentation

Rhetoric is an important component of argumentation and vice versa. Rhetoric, from a linguistic point of view, has developed models to organize claim justifications, argument supports and attacks in a structured way with the goal of being as efficient and convincing as possible. Planning issues are essential in rhetoric. For example, starting with the less prominent justifications and ending with the most crucial ones with which almost everybody agrees is a frequent strategy to convince an audience. This planning activity may also anticipate attacks from opponents by presenting them and refuting them. Rhetoric also deals with linguistic aspects such as lexical choice and syntactic structure. Finally, rhetoric offers a unified view of linguistic expression paired with non-verbal means such as gestures, mimics, various forms of sounds and images. Rhetoric is therefore a major component of argumentation in real contexts. In this section, the main features of rhetoric are introduced. There is an important literature on rhetoric, starting from [PER 58].

3.4.1. Rhetoric and communication

Rhetoric, as well as argumentation, is based on the following three main communication paradigms:

  • – demonstration: which develops an impersonal mode. It uses facts, axioms and inference rules. There are various types of logics and forms of demonstrations, whose goal is to identify whether a statement is true or false;
  • – dialectic: which is the art of dialog. Dialectic does not deal with truth, but with what is probable. However, it uses rigorous protocols, norms and forms of reasoning to reach the best consensus on a topic. Dialectic uses argumentation in situations such as debates, negotiation or mediation;
  • – sophism: which is typically the area of duplicity and cheating. It is based on false assumptions that, nevertheless, seem plausible to an audience.

The ideal model of an argumentation is organized as follows:

  1. 1) confrontation stage: recognition of a difference of opinion on a certain topic that is made explicit and unambiguous;
  2. 2) opening stage: decision to try to resolve the issue following a number of argumentation and cooperativity rules (Chapter 2) on which the different parties agree;
  3. 3) argumentation stage: defense of standpoints via argumentation rules, argumentation schemes and conventions. This stage uses facts to develop justifications;
  4. 4) conclusion stage: assessment of the differences or agreement on a compromise.

In these stages, argumentation and explanation may co-exist in order, for example, to bring new information to the opponent or to change his/her beliefs.

The main features claimed and developed by rhetoric to be crucial in any argumentation process can be summarized as follows:

  • – language appropriateness and correctness: these requirements concern, in particular, lexical choice, the syntax of utterances, the use of an appropriate genre, for example, judicial, deliberative, epidictic (to make the panegyric of someone). At a more global level, features related to style such as being clear (no ambiguity), being pleasant to listen or to read (metaphors, figures of speech), being well illustrated, etc. are also crucial to build a convincing argumentation.
  • – appropriate level of style depending on the situation and the audience: simple (based on logos and proofs), middle (based on ethos with the goal to give a good impression to the audience) and noble (based on pathos), which is mainly used for persuasion or in special circumstances.
  • – use of appropriate figures of speech, which concern words (play on words for effects), construction (e.g. ellipsis), meaning (metaphors), thought (develops the relation between the orator, its topic, and the discourse using forms of irony or emphasis, for example).

The remainder of this section develops the main features of rhetoric: logos, ethos and pathos and their conceptual, communication and linguistic features.

3.4.2. Logos: the art of reasoning and of constructing demonstrations

Logos is the most rational component of rhetoric. It introduces deduction and reasoning into a discourse that is not necessarily very rational. The motivation is that some forms of logical reasoning are often necessary to establish controversies. There are several strategies to develop an argumentation. They depend on the profile of the audience and on the difficulty to justify the claim at stake. The development of an appropriate plan to deliver justifications is crucial. Such plans are a matter of experience rather than the use of preestablished, ready-made plans. Content planning and defining the macrostructure of a text or an oral presentation is a topic that has been addressed in length in natural language generation (NLG).

The main linguistic features of logos are the argumentative value of negation and negative expressions, the impact of interrogative forms, in particular the use of rhetorical questions, the syntactic forms which are used and in particular the use of left-extraposition (moving constituents to the left in a sentence) to create focus effects, the use of reported speech and citations to refer to different types of authors (e.g. to develop arguments from authority), the use of modals, etc.

The impact of lexical choice is very important in an argumentative discourse. The weight of an argument may depend on the terms that are used because of their ease of understanding and familiarity for an audience, their potential connotations, for example, the opposition between the terms wild and uncontrolled, the induced irony or their a priori polarity. For example, systematically using positively oriented terms, even in a context with high controversies may shed a positive light on the discourse even if this positive character is not totally motivated. In the same range of ideas, lexical re-interpretations and semantic variations (e.g. war instead of conflict of interest or men who fight with each other may radically change perspectives).

Besides the purely linguistic aspects, the logos aspect includes conceptual aspects, in particular:

  • – the development of implicit aspects in the reasoning and planning process. The goal is to leave the opponents to make their own inferences. This often induces an argumentation with fewer possibilities for debate: what is implicit is indeed viewed as obvious. The listeners or opponents probably agree with it or make their own inferences concerning what is left implicit. It is important for the orator to have a good analysis of the shared knowledge and beliefs of their opponents in order to use them as much as possible;
  • – the use of presuppositions, which can often be reconstructed linguistically. This approach is more objective than using implicit elements, however, it has a stronger persuasion effect. Implicit elements can be reconstructed via Grice’s implicature system, when presuppositions obey cooperation maxims. This system is useful to reconstruct the missing premises of an argumentation;
  • – the use of appropriate connectors that bind two explicit statements. The most frequently encountered connectors are but, however, because, notwithstanding, nevertheless. Each of them is used in a specific context: they indeed have their own pragmatic profile and implications.

3.4.3. Ethos: the orator profile

Ethos is a crucial component in dialogues and debates. It mainly deals with the communication parameters of the orator, in particular his/her behavior (e.g. listens to the audience, is cheerful), his/her personality (e.g. attractive, happy, optimistic), how s/he speaks (e.g. in a fluid manner, with hesitation, with the help of notes), how s/he is dressed, what kind of facial expressions are used, possibly her/his environment (lights, scenery), whether s/he is sitting or standing up, etc.

Ethos is a major parameter of strength and persuasion. The goal of ethos is to develop emotion and seduction to gain the empathy of the opponent(s) or of the audience. To reach this goal, ethos stimulates the listeners’ imagination, while taking into account, as much as possible, their desires and expectations. Another feature, which reinforces the stability and the veracity of the arguments, is to adhere as much as possible to the doxa, i.e. what is commonly admitted, even if it is debatable.

To reach this goal, the speaker must have a good analysis of the expectations of his audience and of the psychological profile of his opponent(s) to behave correctly and to follow the audience expectations. There are many examples, for example in advertising, where nice web pages are developed to make readers dream, with a focus on their desires.

From a linguistic point of view, ethos is also concerned with lexical choice aspects and the syntax of sentences. These linguistic elements closely interact with non-verbal elements such as gestures, jokes and metaphors. Doxa is marked by specific marks such as it has always been the case, as we all know and we all agree that P is true. In some cases, rhetorical questions can also be used to mark doxa.

3.4.4. Pathos: how to persuade an audience

Pathos is the art of persuading an audience and of touching the opponent. It is the audience dimension of rhetoric, this complements the features of ethos, but these two aspects of rhetoric are closely related.

The first characteristic of pathos is the way the orator acts on an audience or on her/his opponents. The main elements deployed by pathos is how to touch an audience, make it become angry, frightened or, conversely, make it happy, feel safe or confident. The orator must care not to make confusions with her/his own emotions. Pathos is not necessarily a very honest and transparent process. It uses two opposite facets: to convince (rational component of the audience) and to persuade (irrational component). Pathos is based on the fact that emotions are also value judgments of a high strength in a cognitive perspective. Emotions can then be “argued”.

One of the major risks is that pathos, via its persuasion effects, deeply affects the rationality (logos) of the argumentation. The risk then is that the audience develops a feeling of trickery. There are a few linguistic cues which are typical of trickery, lies and audience manipulation. They are characterized by the use of repetitions and terms that develop insistence such as really, completely, definitely, absolutely, totally and truthful. These also insist on the truthfulness of statements, which are not necessarily true.

Pathos makes a systematic use of ad hominen and ad populum argument schemes to attack opponents and discredit them. This strategy deeply affects the overall quality of logos. Pathos must be paired with references to moral values to get all of its impact and power. These values may depend on the argumentation context. In situations such as debates, negotiation, mediation and warning of a danger (ad baculum), values may be quite different.

In conceptual terms, pathos develops emotions that are frequently in relation with the audience’s preferred images, topics and beliefs (e.g. children = innocence) or major social schemes. The challenge is that the same images can produce very different emotions depending on how they are presented in an argumentation and how emotion is constructed. Similarly, the rejection of emotions can be a positive strategy in an argumentation, even if this rejection is artificial or fake. This is realized by means of typical terms that reverse the polarity of the arguments. Emotion is lexicalized with specific linguistic and pragmatic marks. Other elements typical of emotion expression include style, emphasis, rhythm and repetitions.

..................Content has been hidden....................

You can't read the all page of ebook, please click here login for view all page.
Reset