CHAPTER 3
Capital Ideas

One of the great ironies embedded inside the structure of all complex systems is that they sow the seeds of their own demise. Such is the case for modern economies and bull markets. The collapse of the Western financial system in 2008 demonstrated beyond a shadow of a doubt that there are internal contradictions embedded in how modern capitalist societies organize themselves. The free market mantras that permitted lightly regulated financial industries to conduct business in reckless and self-serving ways over the three decades leading up to the crisis were thoroughly discredited by the need for Western governments to bail out their largest financial institutions.

The seeds of destruction were primarily ideological; they grew out of widely accepted but flawed ways of thinking about capital, economic growth, and financial regulation. Instead of basing economic growth on a modified free market model that privileges concepts such as equity, transparency, production, and prudent and limited regulation, those in positions of influence chose a radical free market path of debt, opacity, speculation, and wholesale deregulation. There were two problems with this approach. First, the United States does not have a genuine free market; government regulation and crony capitalism play an enormous role in distorting incentives and interfering with the free market. Second, this regime was based on the radical error of pretending that markets are efficient and investors are rational when precisely the opposite is true.

The choices did not have to be as stark as that—there is a middle ground that can serve the interests of all economic stakeholders. But the pendulum clearly swung too far in favor of the radical free market model. And after the financial crisis, the results lay in ruins all around us: insolvent banks, disenfranchised workers, impoverished state, local, and federal governments, a poisoned planet, embarrassed regulators, hypocritical and corrupt legislators crying for retribution between visits to the campaign feeding trough on Wall Street, and a public that lost trust in government. A capitalist system inherently prone to booms and busts became even more prone to disequilibrium. In order to understand what happened and in order to rebuild a more resilient system, we must dig deeply into basic economic principles and reevaluate them.

There are many influential economic thinkers whose work would greatly benefit market participants. In order to better understand the death of capital in 2008, four particular thinkers are worthy of extended discussion—Adam Smith, Karl Marx, John Maynard Keynes, and Hyman Minsky. But these thinkers need to be approached in a way that transcends economics. Three of the seminal works of economic theory that are examined in this chapter—The Wealth of Nations (1776); Capital (1867); and The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money (1936)—are best considered intellectual performances that far exceed the discipline of economics and qualify as both great literature and great philosophy that have influenced intellectual debate in a variety of disciplines for generations. Each of these works has been analyzed and debated endlessly in academic and policy circles for years and continues to provide rich material for thinkers in a variety of disciplines. This is a tribute to the genius of their authors and the fact that the concepts discussed in these works are subject to multiple interpretations and misinterpretations.

What follows is a highly selective if not idiosyncratic reading of the aspects of these seminal thinkers that ties together their interpretations of some of the key characteristics of capital, capitalism, and markets. It is my contention that these intellectual giants provide insights into the nature of capital that are largely misunderstood by investors, regulators, and policymakers. The result is that little progress has been made in effectively managing the boom and bust nature of free market capitalism, which in turn has caused capitalism to fall far short of reaching its full potential to contribute to the growth and welfare of human society.

The first two thinkers, Adam Smith and Karl Marx, stand at opposite sides of the ideological spectrum yet share an enormous amount of common ground. These philosophers remain two of the most insightful students of capitalism long after their work began to influence the world. Adam Smith saw capitalism as a force for good, while Marx saw it as a cause of conflict and abuse. Their work provides important insights into the characteristics that render capital inherently unstable and crisis-prone. What follows is not intended to be a complete discussion of these two complex thinkers; rather, it is an attempt to draw out some of their key ideas as they affect the modern understanding of financial markets.

Smith and Marx speak to several of the key intellectual and moral underpinnings of our economic collapse. Both men describe markets governed by complex human relationships that at their basic level are strongly affected by people seeking social approbation. They also make powerful statements about the fact that human economic interactions, and the relationships between money and goods, are highly mediated. In discussing these two thinkers, I hope to illuminate some of the forces that drive economic actors to behave in certain ways that are ultimately very harmful to the long-term interests of society. By better understanding the profound truths that Smith and Marx described, we can hopefully address some of these flaws more effectively as we work to design a more productive economic system that serves the interests of all of us, not just the most privileged among us.

The last two thinkers wrote more recently and were particularly prominent in recent discussions surrounding the financial crisis of 2008. John Maynard Keynes and his most important modern interpreter, Hyman Minsky, understood the psychological aspects of capitalism as well as anybody who ever studied the system. In fact, Keynes may best be considered the greatest psychologist of economics, a mantle that Minsky assumed in warning of the dangers of financial instability. By focusing on the ways in which economic actors react to their environment, both men not only demonstrate great insight into human behavior but provide a road map for investors and regulators charged with navigating financial markets. Students of Minsky were undoubtedly the best prepared to recognize the unstable financing structures that led to the 2008 crisis, how these structures developed, and why such structures are endemic to the nature of capitalism and remain a serious threat.

The United States spent the last four decades—the 1980s, 1990s, 2000s, and now the 2010s—with an increasingly leveraged economic system whose primary occupation was to conceal declining productivity and weakening profitability from the eyes of investors and regulators while enriching a small elite.1 By the end of the Bush II administration, the United States faced the most serious economic downturn since the Great Depression of the 1930s as its banking system lay broken and major industries such as housing and automobile manufacturing were on the verge of total collapse. The policies followed during the Obama administration and other governments around the world to set the global economy on a path of sustainable economic growth utterly failed to right the ship. It is necessary to analyze the deep structures of capital and capitalism in order to understand what happened and chart a new pathway to recovery. There is no better place to start such a study than the work of Adam Smith.

Adam Smith and the Tyranny of Crowds

When Adam Smith wrote about markets, he pictured in his mind the markets he walked in the streets of the eighteenth-century Scottish cities where he grew up (Kirkcaldy), attended school (Glasgow), and made his career (Edinburgh). These were smelly, bustling street markets filled with a huge assortment of physical goods and characters drawn out of a Charles Dickens novel. The historian Fernand Braudel gives us a vivid picture of the types of markets that Adam Smith experienced every day, filled with:

[a] varied and active proletariat: pea-shellers, who had a reputation for being inveterate gossips; frog-skinners, . . . porters, sweepers, carters, unlicensed pedlars of both sexes, fussy controllers who passed on their derisory offices from father to son; secondhand dealers, peasants and peasant women recognizable by their dress, as were respectable townswomen looking for a bargain, servant-girls who had worked out, so their employers complained, how to make something out of the shopping-money (to shoe the mule, ferrer la mule as they said); bakers selling coarse bread on the marketplace, butchers whose displays of meat encumbered the streets and squares, wholesalers . . . selling fish, butter and cheese in large quantities; tax-collectors. And everywhere of course were the piles of produce, slabs of butter, heaps of vegetables, pyramids of cheeses, fruit, wet fish, game, meat which the butcher cut up on the spot, unsold books whose pages were used to wrap up purchases. From the countryside there also came straw, hay, wood, wool, hemp, flax, and even fabrics woven on village looms.2

The overwhelming features of these markets were the smells, the sounds of people and animals, humans moving to and fro, the interaction among butchers and bakers and tradesmen buying and selling their goods. Smith had a very specific conception of what markets looked like and how the people in them behaved. Such markets still exist today, primarily in less developed countries but also in some developed countries where they remain quaint reminders of how people used to live. They are colorful emblems of the basic human relationships that remain the foundation of all economic exchanges.

Of course, the markets that drive economic activity today look very different. Physical markets of the type that Adam Smith knew are largely a sideshow or curiosity in modern Western societies. The markets that fuel modern global economies do not involve the trading of physical goods. They are largely antiseptic, electronic arenas where the only strong odors arise from the excesses of the night before. The primary commodities exchanged in modern markets are electronic bytes that represent stocks, bonds, mortgages, corporate bank loans, and currencies or, increasingly, complex derivative contracts that represent an interest in these financial instruments. To the extent there is a strong physical dimension to the proceedings, it is found in the impressive appearance that the technology that facilitates this trading assumes in the form of long rows of traders and their sleek computers and electronic computer screens. The sight is indeed impressive but has virtually no representational relationship with the underlying economic objects that are being exchanged. Unlike the street markets in eighteenth-century Glasgow or Edinburgh, the buyers and sellers rarely deal with each other face to face. Instead, they speak on the telephone or e-mail or text each other. Their communication is highly mediated; it is, to a large extent, impersonal and disembodied. This does not mean that their relationship is completely bereft of personal contact, but there is a great deal of truth to the concept that the age of gentlemanly capitalism has passed. The real question is whether the age of human capitalism has gone with it. The answer to that question is a resounding no.

Every day, on electronic trading floors around the globe, trillions of dollars of trades are effected on the basis of verbal agreements that are only later solidified into binding written contracts. A trader’s word is literally his or her bond. A simple “you’re done” is sufficient to signal that a trade is complete, whether that trade is for a million or a billion dollars of value. Despite the fact that the relationships between buyers and sellers as well as the goods they are trading are largely disembodied, a remarkably small percentage of trades end up being seriously disputed. Part of the reason for this is that technology allows for discussions between traders to be recorded. Another reason is far more elemental—nobody will deal with a trader who doesn’t keep his or her word, and word circulates very quickly about who is trustworthy and who is not in the tight-knit trading community. There are protocols that have developed over time that must be followed if traders are going to be able to make a living. All of the computer terminals in the world can’t erase the crucial human element that lies at the bottom of every single trade. This is one reason that Adam Smith has a great deal to teach us.

Adam Smith, of course, is best known as the author of what many people consider to be the bible of capitalism, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations (1776). But two decades earlier, he wrote an arguably more important book, a treatise on moral philosophy entitled The Theory of Moral Sentiments (1759). In his earlier book, Smith sought to lay out the basis for moral conduct in human society and argued that people’s concern for the opinions of others ultimately leads them to act in moral and civilized ways. In Smith’s worldview, the process by which men develop a moral sense is very similar to the manner in which they develop markets. Both institutions—human societyand human markets—are the result of human beings interacting with each other in ways that make them feel good about themselves by fulfilling their own needs. Just as the desire to fulfill material needs leads to the exchange of goods and hence the development of markets, the desire to fulfill emotional needs leads men and women to be sensitive to the views of others and thereby to develop a moral sense. Neither the markets nor the morals they develop are perfect; in fact, both are constant works-in-process that are flawed, subject to emotion, and unstable. Over time, Smith believes that the process of developing and refining a moral sense leads to the formation of order in morality and markets that is superior to other forms because it fulfills human needs better than other forms. In other words, Smith argues that such a system is not only a realistic description of how men and women behave, but it is an optimal system. That does not mean, however, that these systems can simply be allowed to operate without laws or institutions. Rather, Smith was searching for the optimal institutional framework in which people’s innate qualities could be put to the best use. Taking people as they were (or, as he saw them, warts and all), Smith was trying to design a world that would make people the best they could be.3

In The Wealth of Nations, Smith famously wrote that “[i]t is not from the benevolence of the butcher, the brewer, or the baker, that we expect our dinner, but from their regard to their own interest.”4 Yet Smith’s project was not to unconditionally praise an “invisible hand”5 of self-interest guiding free-market behavior, but to identify those institutions and processes that could provide human beings with the best opportunity to act in constructive, decent, and moral ways. He believed that a free market in which men and women could demonstrate their worth by exchanging goods and services was among the most important of those institutions. The freedom to earn a living through exchange would, in Smith’s view, give individuals the best opportunity to avoid the types of dependency on others that leads to immoral behavior.

Smith’s view that people base their conduct on their concern for the opinion of others is wholly relativistic. As such, it provides both wisdom and warning. The wisdom comes from Smith’s recognition that human beings are strongly driven by social approbation. We desperately want to feel that we are part of a group that accepts us. And the first step to accomplishing that is understanding how others feel about us. From the first words of The Theory of Moral Sentiments, Smith focuses on our concern for the feelings of others. “How selfish soever man may be supposed, there are evidently some principles in his nature, which interest him in the fortune of others, and render their happiness necessary to him, though he derives nothing from it, except the pleasure of seeing it.” He continues, “[t]hat we often derive sorrow from the sorrow of others, is a matter of fact too obvious to require any instances to prove it.” The way we try to understand how other people feel is to put ourselves in their place. “As we have no immediate experience of what other men feel, we can form no idea of the manner in which they are affected, but by conceiving what we ourselves should feel in the like situation.” Continuing, Smith writes, “That this is the source of our fellow-feeling for the misery of others, that it is by changing places in fancy with the sufferer, that we come either to conceive or to be affected by what he feels.”6

In order to judge the feelings of others, Smith tries to establish an objective standard (similar to the “prudent man” rule discussed in Chapter 8 of this book) that he terms the “impartial spectator.” It is from the standpoint of this impartial spectator that others should be judged:

We conceive ourselves as acting in the presence of a person quite candid and equitable, of one who has no particular relation either to ourselves, or to those whose interests are affected by our conduct, who is neither father, nor brother, nor friend either to them or to us, but is merely a man in general, an impartial spectator who considers our conduct with the same indifference with which we regard that of other people.7

In Smith’s world, all moral judgments rely on the judgment of this independent man.8

As the scholar Dennis Rasmussen points out, Smith understood that undue concern with the opinions of others could “lead to a corruption of people’s moral sentiments, selfishly motivated appeals to others’ self-interest, and a good deal of ostentation.”9 Social approbation does not always bring out the best in people. Too often, people worship the wrong idols. Smith’s statement that undue admiration for the rich is the source of the corruption of our moral sentiments, which is found at the beginning of this book, speaks an uncomfortable truth that should be posted on the entryway of every financial institution and government building in the world. Smith’s philosophical project is aimed at fashioning a just society out of the fact that people are unduly concerned with the opinions of others, and that these opinions steer them to admire the wrong moral attributes in other people. But instead of simply identifying this as a flaw, Smith attempts to use worship of the rich and powerful as a basis for fashioning a more just society.

Smith believes that a commercial society is particularly well-suited to such a project. In a commercial society, people are dependent on one another to work together to meet their needs. They generally cannot meet their needs alone (even Thoreau ventured into Concord from Walden Pond regularly to replenish his stores). For this reason, people have a strong incentive to work together and depend on each other. As Dennis Rasmussen writes, for this reason Smith believed that “commerce encourages traits like reliability, decency, honesty, cooperativeness, a commitment to keeping one’s promises, and a strict adherence to society’s norms of justice.”10 In Smith’s view, it is incumbent upon people in a market society to conduct themselves in a moral way in order to be able to participate in and benefit from commercial activity.11 It is in people’s interest to engage in good behavior because that will better help them fill their needs.

Of course, Smith was striving for an ideal, and commercial life is not so simple. The warning concealed in Smith’s words comes from his failure to identify any independent moral standard as the basis for human conduct. Instead of basing morality on natural law, religion, or reason, Smith argued that moral conduct originates entirely in human beings’ feelings or sentiments. The rules of morality result from feelings, not vice versa. Smith writes:

It is thus that the general rules of morality are formed. They are ultimately founded upon experience of what, in particular instances, our moral faculties, our natural sense of merit and propriety, approve or disapprove of. We do not originally approve or condemn particular actions, because, upon examination, they appear to be agreeable or inconsistent with a certain general rule. The general rule, on the contrary, is formed by finding from experience that all actions of a certain kind, or circumstanced in a certain manner, are approved or disapproved of. . . . Those general rules…are all formed from the experience we have had of the effects which actions of all different kinds naturally produce upon us.12

These feelings are not only our own—they are what we imagine others would feel watching our conduct. “If we saw ourselves in the light in which others see us, or in which they would see us if they knew all, a reformation would generally be unavoidable. We could not otherwise endure the sight.”13 By making the opinions of others the standard by which we judge ourselves rather than some independent or objective moral standard, we risk surrendering ourselves to the madness of crowds. After all, history has demonstrated repeatedly that groups are particularly susceptible to flawed thinking.

There is a dark side to this concurrence-seeking ethos that has played itself out throughout history. It lies at the heart of the type of herd thinking that causes phenomena such as investment bubbles and, in its most pernicious form, genocide. In his classic study, Groupthink, Irving Janis identified strong consensus-seeking behavior as one of the main causes of defective decision-making in classic policy disasters such as the Kennedy and Johnson administrations’ actions with respect to the Vietnam War and the Bay of Pigs.14 The desire of members of a group to be accepted by others, which lies at the heart of Adam Smith’s theory of moral sentiments, tends to silence dissenting voices, limit the airing of unpopular views, and lead to poor decision-making.

Permitting the opinions of others to govern important human activities is a highly problematic enterprise. It is another version of conceding all wisdom to the free market. But crowds, and markets, often get things terribly wrong; in point of fact, they often act irrationally. Smith observed that human behavior and institutions evolve through the interaction of human beings attempting to satisfy their emotional or economic needs. However true this may be as a matter of fact, it need not be dispositive as a matter of prescription. Some human impulses are contrary to the health of the larger community, even deviant and dangerous. Greed and fear, two human drives that govern a great deal of market behavior, are directly contrary to the operation of healthy markets and a productive economy if they are not properly reined in. Adam Smith described how men and markets develop and believed that markets could be designed with the proper governing institutions to contain man’s worst instincts. One of the purposes of The Committee to Destroy the World is to evaluate the failure to develop the right kinds of institutional structures to manage the tyranny of crowds.

Smith wrote a long time ago, but the world has not passed him by. In many ways, the world is still trying to catch up to him. We are still trying to design the proper institutions and markets that will allow man’s best attributes to flourish while governing the demons of his nature. Recent events demonstrate that the dark side of human nature—greed, fear, arrogance, stupidity—remains a formidable foe that places humankind’s welfare at risk at regular intervals. The social approbation that Smith identified as the primary basis of man’s moral sentiments still drives many peoples’ behavior, especially their economic behavior. Sadly, free markets are all too imperfect governors of human behavior. The unfortunate truth is that financial crises, which are occurring with increasing, not decreasing, frequency are the result of deeply embedded traits of human nature and recurring failures to regulate our worst instincts. Two-and-a-half centuries after Adam Smith, mankind still needs to be protected from itself.

One of the frustrating lessons of markets is that investors continually ignore Groucho Marx’s sage advice not to join any club that would accept them as members. Financial markets should often be avoided entirely, but investors cannot help themselves when they see everyone around them clamoring to participate. Today’s markets are obviously far different from the more intimate ones that Smith walked in eighteenth-century Kirkcaldy, Glasgow, and Edinburgh. The products and economic actors he described—butchers and bakers, pin and woolen coat makers—vividly captured his frame of reference. Smith had personal, first-hand interactions with the men and women hawking their wares in these teeming and chaotic markets that somehow organized themselves into institutions that made food, clothing, and other goods available to Scottish society.

Today, the trading of goods has been replaced by the trading of bytes, and the personal relationships that defined mercantile relationships in the eighteenth century are abraded by technology and radical changes in the forms that capital assumes. But at the heart of these markets still lie the personal and social relationships between human beings that Adam Smith identified as the central feature of all human institutions. It is incumbent upon us today to take his wisdom and apply it to the new outward forms that markets assume with the understanding that the essential inward forms that drive markets are still governed by human relationships.

The Fallacy of Composition

Another aspect of Adam Smith’s view of how moral sentiments develop raises another set of challenges for promoters of free markets. Smith’s description of men developing their moral senses in The Theory of Moral Sentiments tells a story of trial and error:

In order to produce this concord [of sentiments], as nature teaches the spectators to assume the circumstances of the person principally concerned, so she teaches this last in some measure to assume those of the spectators. As they are continually placing themselves in his situation, and thence conceiving emotions similar to what he feels; so he is as constantly placing himself in theirs, and thence conceiving some degree of that coolness about his own fortune, with which he is sensible that they will view it. As they are constantly considering what they themselves would feel, if they actually were the sufferers, so he is constantly led to imagine in what manner he would be affected if he was only one of the spectators of his own situation. As their sympathy makes them look at it in some measure with his eyes, so his sympathy makes him look at it, in some measure, with theirs, especially when in their presence, and acting under their observation: and, as the reflected passion which he thus conceives is much weaker than the original one, it necessarily abates the violence of what he felt before he came into their presence, before he began to recollect in what manner they would be affected by it, and to view his situation in this candid and impartial light.15

Rather than beginning from a set of general rules, the rules of morality are developed from the experience of observing other people and accepting and rejecting the reactions to these observations. This is very similar to Smith’s description of how markets develop in The Wealth of Nations, as Professor James R. Otteson argues very persuasively in Adam Smiths Marketplace of Life. Professor Otteson writes that Smith’s view of human nature:

[S]hows human morality to display four central substantive characteristics: it is a system that rises unintentionally from the actions of individuals, it displays an unconscious and slow development from informal to formal as needs and interests change and progress, it depends on regular exchange among freely associating people, and it receives its initial and ongoing impetus from the desires of the people who use it. But this account also adheres to a framework that . . . has the central elements of a system of unintended order modeled on an economic market.16

This process of observation and imitation leads human beings to adapt their behavior over time into modes that allow them to work together and build a functioning society. It is a process that is basic to many complex living systems.

In fact, Smith’s view of the development of human morality is very similar to the process of self-organizing criticality described by Stuart Kauffman in his brilliant book on the organization of complex systems, At Home in the Universe. Kauffman argues that:

Laws of complexity spontaneously generate much of the order of the natural world. . . . We have all known that simple physical systems exhibit spontaneous order: an oil droplet in water forms a sphere; snowflakes exhibit their evanescent sixfold symmetry. What is new is that the range of spontaneous order is enormously greater than we have supposed. Profound order is being discovered in large, complex, and apparently random systems. I believe that this emergent order underlies not only the origin of life itself, but much of the order seen in organisms today.17

Kauffman then describes some of the broad processes of natural life that he believes are echoed in economic systems.

Life, then, unrolls in an unending procession of change, with small and large bursts of speciations, and small and large bursts of extinctions, ringing out the old, ringing in the new. If this view is correct, then the patterns of life’s bursts and burials are caused by internal processes, endogenous and natural. These patterns of speciations and extinctions, avalanching across ecosystems and time, are somehow self-organized, somehow collective emergent phenomena, somehow natural expressions of the laws of complexity we seek. . . . No small matter these small and large avalanches of creativity and destruction, for the natural history of life for the past 550 million years has echoes of the same phenomena at all levels: from ecosystems to economic systems undergoing technological evolution, in which avalanches of new goods and technologies emerge and drive old ones extinct.18

His conclusion is that “the fate of all complex adapting systems in the biosphere—from single cells to economies—is to evolve to a natural state between order and chaos, a grand compromise between structure and surprise.”19 If this is, in fact, the way societies and markets evolve—and there is a great deal of evidence that this is the case—then these insights are extremely important for our understanding of financial crises, our approaches to managing them, and our hopes of preventing them or at least of mitigating the permanent damage they inflict.

Financial markets in a capitalist system are marked by constant change and adaptability at every level of operation. The creation of new financial products is often a response to a market inefficiency that can be exploited for profit. Sometimes that market inefficiency results from regulation, and other times from changes in the nonfinancial economy. But market changes begin with the actions of individual economic actors who are seeking to solve a problem and, in a capitalist system, earn a profit at the same time. Individual economic actors behave based on their view of their own self-interest. There is a strong pro-cyclical, or path dependent, character to this activity. This is the essence of capitalism. Smith’s and Kauffman’s views of human processes and markets seem to describe the type of pro-cyclical behavior that sows the seeds of financial crises.

The problem is that this regime runs into something known as the “fallacy of composition,” which teaches us that the sum of individual decisions often does not add up to a beneficial result for the system as a whole. In fact, individual decisions that can be shown to be rational when considered individually often tend to lead to disastrous results when aggregated. Again, these results should not be surprising; in fact, they are predictable if you know where to look for the warning signs. In economic terms, this phenomenon is closely associated with pro-cyclical behavior, which reinforces the existing direction of economic forces and markets. The classic example of the “fallacy of composition” was described by John Maynard Keynes in The General Theory, where he described how the rational behavior of individuals reducing their spending during an economic downturn will exacerbate that downturn and potentially lead to a depression (this is famously known as “the paradox of thrift”). In a market in which individuals are free to make their own decisions based on their self-interest, decisions based on rational individual profit motives (which are generally reasonably short-term in nature) ultimately tend to lead to instability rather than stability when they are aggregated. In certain respects this is also the great lesson of the economist Hyman Minsky, who taught that stability breeds instability. When the economy and the financial markets appear to be stable, it is perfectly rational for investors to feel that it is prudent to take more risk. The problem lies in the fact that everybody tends to increase their risk appetite at the same time, which raises overall systemic risk to dangerous levels. In fact, history demonstrates repeatedly that risk at any time should only be increased cautiously because many other people are likely to be increasing theirs at the same time, magnifying the overall risk context in which the individual decisions are being made.

Investment contrarians fancy themselves capable of separating themselves from the crowd and investing in an anticyclical manner. In today’s world, however, where investments are driven by computerized money flows and quantitative investment strategies, it has become more difficult than ever to separate oneself from the crowd logistically even if one can do so psychologically. Larger investment portfolios, in particular, are captive to market movements unless they exercise extraordinary vigilance in spotting pro-cyclical market behavior and structure their investments in a manner that allows them to liquidate positions easily. As 2008 demonstrated, few large portfolios are capable of doing so, which explains the similarity in negative performance that occurred during that annus horribilis. Only investors who were able to spot market excesses born of pro-cyclical investment behavior that were going on for years were able to defend themselves against the inevitable downward correlation of all asset classes that occurred when the markets could no longer sustain excessive valuations and leverage.

Karl Marx and the Origins of Opacity

It is unfortunate that many conservative thinkers dismiss the work of Karl Marx due to the damage it has caused in the hands of tyrants because it has a great deal to teach us about the system he criticized. There is a deep and bitter irony in the fact that this deep reader of man’s economic nature—and arguably the most astute interpreter of capitalism despite the tragic misreadings his work has engendered—sits at the opposite end of the ideological spectrum from Adam Smith. But a careful reading of Adam Smith and Karl Marx shows that these two thinkers share much more than is commonly believed. As we pick up the pieces of a world economy that was almost destroyed by the credit crisis of 2008, Marx’s stinging comment about history repeating itself first as tragedy and then as farce mocks capitalism’s compulsion to repeat the mistakes of the past. Marx’s economic theories are highly complex and go far beyond the concept of class struggle for which he is best known. Indeed, it would be difficult to discuss the death of capital without addressing one of capital’s most important critics. Despite the proclivity on the part of conservative economic and political commentators to dismiss Marx as a crackpot, his writings offer profound insights into capitalism and capitalist processes. In fact, his work attracted more mainstream attention in the wake of the financial crisis.20

For the purposes of understanding how Western capitalism came to consume itself at the dawn of the twenty-first century, there are few better places to retreat than the writings of Marx. Three of Marx’s insights are particularly worthy of note.

  1. Marx’s conception of capital as a process and not a static object, which renders capitalism a system filled with contradictions that render it highly dynamic and unstable.
  2. Marx’s conceptualization of money and monetary forms as fetishes—indirect expressions of underlying social and economic relations whose meaning is obscured and distorted by their mediation through the form of money in its increasingly complex and derivative forms.
  3. Marx’s insight that value is a highly changeable and unstable concept.

All three of these concepts bear on the increasingly complex forms that money assumed in the late twentieth and early twenty-first century. The more complex and opaque that forms of money became, the more unstable concepts of value (both economic and moral) also became. And with unstable value came not only unstable markets but a highly unstable economy.

Capital Is a Process, Not a Thing

Marx’s major work, Capital, is a tough go for most modern readers. Perhaps the best way to approach this monstrously large and convoluted work is as a major intellectual and literary achievement that happens to discuss economics. One of Marx’s recent biographers, Francis Wheen, suggests why this is appropriate: “By the time he wrote Das Kapital, [Marx] was pushing out beyond conventional prose into radical literary collage—juxtaposing voices and quotations from mythology and literature, from factory inspectors’ reports and fairy tales, in the manner of Ezra Pound’s Cantos or Eliot’s The Waste Land. Das Kapital is as discordant as Schoenberg, as nightmarish as Kafka.”21 He could have added that the book is as encyclopedic and apocalyptic as the American masterpiece, Moby Dick. Just as Herman Melville’s masterpiece swept away most of the American fiction that preceded it, Capital redefined most earlier economics treatises; after Capital, capitalism and economics never looked the same. The image that most often comes to mind when one thinks about Marx’s description of capitalism in Capital is the “dark Satanic mills” described by the iconoclastic English poet and artist William Blake in his poem of the early 1800s, “Jerusalem.” In Marx’s vision, capitalism is a dark and evil force capable of metamorphosing from one form into another while enslaving the individual. In fact, one of capitalism’s greatest strengths (and instabilities) is its flexibility, its ability to adapt to changing circumstances of history, politics, or geography.

One of Marx’s key economic insights is that capital is a process and not a static object.22 He describes capital variously as “value in process,” “money in process,” and “money which begets money.”23 As such, capital is constantly moving, constantly changing form, and therefore unstable. Marx writes that “[i]t comes out of circulation, enters into it again, preserves and multiplies itself within its circuit, comes back out of it with expanded bulk, and begins the same round ever afresh.”24 In Marx’s formulation, the key characteristic of capital is that it is both money and commodity. “It [capital] . . . always remains money and always commodity. It is in every moment both of the moments which disappear into one another in circulation. But it is this only because it itself is a constantly self-renewing circular course of exchanges.”25 Marx terms commodities a form of “use value” (because they can actually be used or consumed to meet human needs such as hunger), while money is considered a form of “exchange value” (because it can be exchanged for other things of value but cannot itself be consumed to meet human needs).

Because capital assumes both the form of money and the form of commodity in Marx’s world, it is an extremely complex phenomenon. Capital spends its existence moving between these two forms—money and commodity—in order to play its multiple roles in the economy. (At one point, Marx writes, “Capital is money; capital is commodities.”26) As money, it is used as a mechanism of exchange, while as a commodity it is used in its physical form. The transition between these two forms is what we can think of as the liquidity function, and the degree to which the liquidity function is operating smoothly is taken as one indication of the health of markets and the economy.

Yet, as we saw from reading Adam Smith, liquidity can be a misleading sign of health. Just because economic actors are providing liquidity does not mean that the assumptions underlying their actions are justified. As individuals, they may be acting on assumptions that are perfectly reasonable with respect to their individual goals and aspirations. But when these atomized actions are aggregated, they alter the context in which those actions are taken and alter the original assumptions. Marx teaches us another way of understanding how the best laid plans of individuals can turn into the madness of crowds; he offers us a different angle into the “fallacy of composition.” At times, the provision of liquidity is based on flawed understandings or assumptions about the relationship between capital’s roles as money and commodity. Or, put another way, assumptions about the equivalence of the value of capital as money and capital as commodity are incorrect. Since most forms of exchange in an economy are mediated through the form of money, they are indirect and subject to distortion. This is what Keynes means when he says that “much can happen between the cup and the lip.” Economic actors are dealing with inherently unstable referents precisely because they are referents and not the things in themselves (that is, the underlying commodities). And there is no way to avoid this existential condition.

Those who approach the markets from a quantitative standpoint and attempt to model market moves would do well to keep in mind Marx’s fluid view of capital. The value of any financial instrument stays fixed for only a theoretical moment in time (basically the moment at which another party buys it), and stock or bond prices are merely approximations of what the underlying economic referent is worth. This is why economics is better thought of as philosophy or art than science or mathematics, and why even a proper understanding of these latter two disciplines must include a healthy dose of the former two. The presumption of precision that market pundits bring to bear on their predictions of market behavior is highly misleading and renders most market predictions mere palaver.

Our Fetish about Money

In Marx’s formulation, money or exchange value (which again is just one form of capital) is itself a highly complex phenomenon. Man reduces different commodities to money in order to be able to exchange different commodities for each other. Money in this sense is a great equalizer or leveler of value. Money looks like a fixed object but represents something far more complex and dynamic. In Marx’s world, money represents what he variously describes as “congealed labor” or “social hieroglyphics.” What he means by this is that money is the tangible expression of the value that society places on the labor that created the commodity that is represented by money.27 In this sense, labor is itself a form of capital, as noted in Chapter 1.

Marx developed the concept of the “fetishism of commodities” (der Fetischcharakter der Ware) to describe the manner in which commodities are transformed into money. Marx explains that “the products of labor become commodities, social things whose qualities are at once perceptible and imperceptible by the senses.”28 The relationships between human beings as economic actors exchanging goods assume the form of relations between physical objects. Marx continues.

[T]he existence of the things qua commodities, and the value-relation between the products of labor which stamps them as commodities, have absolutely no connection with their physical properties and with the material relations arising therefrom. There it is a definite social relation between men, that assumes, in their eyes, the fantastic form of a relation between things. In order, therefore, to find an analogy, we must have recourse to the mist-enveloped regions of the religious world. In that world the productions of the human brain appear as independent beings endowed with life, and entering into relation both with one another and with the human race.29

Money, the form that all economic exchanges ultimately assumes, is opaque; rather than reveal the underlying social relations that create value, it obscures them.

David Harvey, one of Marx’s best modern readers, writes that “the way things appear to us in daily life can conceal as much as it can reveal about their social meaning.”30 Elsewhere, Harvey writes, “[m]oney and market exchange draws a veil over, ‘masks’ social relationships between things. This condition Marx calls ‘the fetishism of commodities.’ It is one of Marx’s most compelling insights, for it poses the problem of how to interpret the real but nevertheless superficial relationships that we can readily observe in the market place in appropriate social terms.”31 The Polish philosopher Leszek Kolakowski elaborates, writing that “[t]his process whereby social relations masquerade as things or relations between things is the cause of human failure to understand the society in which we live. In exchanging goods for money men involuntarily accept the position that their own qualities, abilities, and efforts do not belong to them but somehow inhere in the objects they have created.”32 Fetishism, according to Kolakowski, describes “the inability of human beings to see their own products for what they are, and their unwitting consent to be enslaved by human power instead of wielding it.”33

Marx was highly aware of the contradictory nature of the reality of economic life captured in the concept of fetishism. In Capital, he writes that “[i]t is . . . just this ultimate money-form of the world of commodities that actually conceals, instead of disclosing, the social character of private labor, and the social relations between the individual producers.”34 In other words, the relationships between the individuals who created the commodities are expressed in the form of the commodities themselves. As a result, the underlying relationships—their meaning, their value, both economic and social—are obscured.

In a financial world of increasing opacity, where money assumes increasingly complex and derivative forms, Marx’s insight deserves special attention. The crisis of 2008, where we discovered that the balance sheets of financial institutions were buried in complex financial derivatives whose value turned out to be highly unstable if not completely indeterminable, was the ultimate lesson in the fetishism of commodities. Money, “the fetish character of commodities,” the physical embodiment of the labor that goes into producing physical things, whether they be crops or widgets, is the primary way in which society comes to a common expression or understanding about the value of material things. Money is the common denominator to which all economic objects are reduced. But when money assumes indecipherable forms, the economic system becomes destabilized. Moreover, the stability or instability of money becomes a measure of the stability or instability of a society on other levels—social, political, and cultural.

There are two types of monetary stability that bear on this issue: the stability of the value of money and the stability of the form of money. Modern markets altered the character of both. The forms of money have grown increasingly complex, primarily though not exclusively through the growth of financial derivatives that both complicate and obscure the meaning of money. Derivatives shake the stability and meaning of money. Instead of simple expressions of debt such as bonds, we have complex and indirect expressions of value such as credit default swaps and collateralized debt obligations. As noted above and as discussed elsewhere in this book, these types of derivatives are a striking example of the fetish of commodities. Even Marx could not have dreamed of a form of money more alienated from labor than these modern financial concoctions. Instead of simple legal tender, we have complex legal contracts that impose contradictory or poorly defined obligations on the parties and in which lenders and borrowers have virtually no connection with each other. Moreover, such financial constructs are the epitome of opacity; their value is not immediately apparent but can be established only after a series of complex calculations. But even that determination is an approximation, for those calculations are themselves subject to a series of mathematical assumptions (not objective certainties) such as present value, discount rate, correlation, and so forth. As a result, the ability to reach general agreement on value is fragile and rather than being scientific becomes highly susceptible to subjective judgment.

Trillions of dollars of financial instruments—stocks, bonds, loans, currencies, and derivatives thereof—are traded daily based on verbal agreements that are only later written down into enforceable legal contracts. It is a tribute to the strength of market customs and practices that it took as long as it did for this system to break down under the weight of new financial instruments whose novel formulations were sufficiently complex to finally disrupt long-established norms of conduct.

The Instability of Value

It should be no surprise, then, that modern markets have the potential to trade with far greater volatility than we have ever seen before. In a world where financial instruments are almost ridiculously complex and increasingly divorced from their underlying economic referents, the concept of what a financial instrument is worth is thrown into question to a greater degree than ever before. The advent of derivatives in particular throws the entire question of value into doubt, creating an opportunity for buyers and sellers to disagree to a wider extent than ever before on the clearing prices for trades. Just a few years before the 2008 financial crisis, Mark C. Taylor wrote a groundbreaking book, Confidence Games: Money and Markets in a World without Redemption, in which he predicted the nature of the crisis that drove markets to the edge:

As derivatives became more abstract and the mathematical formulas for the trading programs more complex, markets began to lose contact with anything resembling the real economy. To any rational investor, it should have been clear that markets were becoming a precarious Ponzi scheme. Contrary to expectation, products originally developed to manage risk increased market volatility and thus intensified the very uncertainty investors were trying to avoid.35

The condition described by Taylor is simply an extension, or exaggeration, of something Marx identified. There is an inherent contradiction in a system that uses money to express value at the same time that it conceals the underlying basis of that value. This creates the opportunity for the users of money to place an incorrect value on the underlying referent.

Marx understood that “[t]he possibility . . . of quantitative incongruity between price and magnitude of value, or the deviation of the former from the latter, is inherent in the price-form itself.”36 He argued that “[t]his is no defect, but, on the contrary, admirably adapts the price-form to a mode of production whose inherent laws can impose themselves as the means of apparently lawless irregularities that compensate one another.”37 Further, “[t]he price-form . . . is not only compatible with the possibility of a quantitative incongruity between magnitude of value and price, i.e., between the former and its expression in money, but it may also conceal a qualitative inconsistency, so much so, that, although money is nothing but the value-form of commodities, price ceases altogether to express value.”38 Marx’s words are particularly apposite in markets in crisis where buyers and sellers are effectively on strike, such as the credit markets in 2008. The problem Marx describes—the incompatibility between value and its form of expression—is exacerbated when the form that money assumes is no longer simple stocks or bonds but far more complex derivative contracts such as credit default swaps or collateral debt obligations. Such instruments are by their very nature more difficult to value due to their inherent complexity. Their value is buffeted on a real-time basis by a variety of factors.

Take the example of a credit default swap: Its value is affected by changes in interest rates, changes in the financial condition of the underlying corporate credit, changes in the financial condition of similar corporations and of the counterparties themselves, supply and demand factors in the market for corporate credit, general economic conditions, and numerous other factors. Moreover, the obligations of the two parties to the contract are defined by a contract that is theoretically standardized but is in practice often bespoke. Accordingly, the ability to agree on the value of such complex instruments is highly compromised. This is one of the prices we pay—in some markets a very high price—for the benefits provided by instruments that are designed to reduce risk by carving it up in ways that distribute it among different market participants. When one considers the complexity of such instruments within the context of what Marx teaches us about the instability of value, one might consider it a miracle that modern markets function at all. It is also a sign of the durability of Marx’s thought that he still has so much to teach us today about capital and capitalism.

John Maynard Keynes

Reading The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money (1936) should be sufficient to disabuse people of the dominant thought paradigms that have guided investors into serial investment disasters in recent years. The concepts of efficient markets or rational investors are rendered mincemeat in the hands of John Maynard Keynes, who writes with a flair that few before or after have been able to match. The irony is that his great wisdom about so many aspects of market behavior has also led to such grotesquely wrong conclusions about how to solve market crises and revive troubled economies. The Keynesian prescription for recovery involves doing more of what was done in the first place to create the crisis: governments spending, printing, and borrowing more money. This may solve the immediate crisis, but it creates long-term imbalances that must be resolved at some point in the future, either through currency devaluation, inflation, or other destabilizing economic and social processes. The problem is that nobody has come up with a viable short-term alternative to the Keynesian solution that does not involve swallowing some very distasteful short-term medicine: bank and business failures, high rates of unemployment, social upheaval, and similar distresses. In the midst of a crisis, Keynes’ prescription makes sense as a means of preventing immediate economic calamity. But it leaves a much bigger mess to clean up in the long run.

Accordingly, Keynesianism is best limited to a prescription for crisis management. As Hyman Minsky stresses in his seminal study of the master, “[i]n 1936, when The General Theory appeared, the world was in the seventh year of the Great Depression.”39 The so-called “classical school of economics” had failed to predict the coming of the depression, and Keynes’ work was an attempt to come up with both an explanation of the causes and proposed solutions. Keynes developed his economic insights within the context of a global collapse of unparalleled depth and duration. The real goal of economic policy should be to minimize the types of imbalances that lead to crisis in the first place, which requires a sophisticated understanding of the processes of capital and the behavior of capitalists.

A careful reading of The General Theory reveals that a book considered to be one of the great economic texts of all time is as much an economics treatise as a psychological primer on how investors behave and what this means for the market as a whole. While the book is filled with its fair share of economic jargon and mathematical formulas, it is primarily memorable for its passages describing human behavior. Perhaps this is what accounts for the fact that its lasting value lies more in its psychological insights into the markets and investor behavior than in its prescriptions for economic policy management. In fact, as noted earlier, its policy prescriptions tend to promulgate economic imbalances. The proper way to employ them proscriptively to reduce the boom and bust cycles of capitalism would be to apply them in a countercyclical manner outside of the crisis context for which they are primarily designed.

Keynes argues that emotion, not reason, is what dominates investment markets. The distinction he draws between speculation and productive investment is based on this view. Keynes defines “speculation” as “the activity of forecasting the psychology of the market” and “enterprise” as “the activity of forecasting the prospective yield of assets over their whole life.”40 Unfortunately, the more developed markets become, the more speculative they become because of the fact that market participants are primarily emotional animals. “As the organisation of investment markets improves,” he writes, “the risk of the predominance of speculation . . . increase[s].”41 Capitalism is highly unstable because it is inherently prone to the imbalances resulting from the fact that capitalists are driven by emotion rather than reason. “The social object of skilled investment should be to defeat the dark forces of time and ignorance which envelop our future. The actual, private object of the most skilled investment to-day is ‘to beat the gun,’ as the Americans so well express it, to outwit the crowd, and to pass the bad, or depreciating, half-crown to the other fellow.”42 In other words, the primary objective of investors is not to determine the fundamental value of an investment; rather, it is to determine what other investors think the value is.

In a famous passage, Keynes compares investing to a newspaper competition in which people have to choose the six prettiest faces out of a hundred photographs:

[P]rofessional investment may be likened to those newspaper competitions in which the competitors have to pick out the six prettiest faces from a hundred photographs, the prize being awarded to the competitor whose choice most nearly corresponds to the average preferences of the competitors as a whole; so that each competitor has to pick, not those faces which he himself finds prettiest, but those which he thinks likeliest to catch the fancy of the other competitors, all of whom are looking at the problem from the same point of view. It is not a case of choosing those which, to the best of one’s judgment, are really the prettiest, nor even those which average opinion genuinely thinks the prettiest. We have reached the third degree where we devote our intelligences to anticipating what average opinion expects the average opinion to be. And there are some, I believe, who practice the fourth, fifth, and higher degrees.43

All financial instruments, not merely stocks and bonds, are subject to this type of beauty contest in which the goal is to pick the most average-looking girl. Keynes writes with respect to interest rates: “the rate of interest is a highly psychological phenomenon . . . The long-term market-rate of interest will depend, not only on the current policy of the monetary authority but also on market expectations concerning its future policy.”44 The problem arises when all the faces look pretty or ugly at the same time. At such times, all anchors of value are lost and men are left to the vagaries of the crowd to guide their behavior. The outcome is rarely favorable for individual investors or for the market as a whole.

Keynes’ famous description of the “animal spirits” that drive financial markets captures his emphasis on the emotional component that he views as central to the investment process. This famous passage is worth quoting in its entirety:

Even apart from the instability due to speculation, there is the instability due to the characteristic of human nature that a large proportion of our positive activities depend on spontaneous optimism rather than on a mathematical expectation, whether moral or hedonistic or economic. Most, probably, of our decisions to do something positive, the full consequences of which will be drawn out over many days to come, can only be taken as a result of animal spirits—of a spontaneous urge to action rather than inaction, and not as the outcome of a weighted average of quantitative benefits multiplied by quantitative probabilities. Enterprise only pretends to itself to be mainly actuated by the statements in its own prospectus, however candid and sincere. Only a little more than an expedition to the South Pole, is it based on an exact calculation of benefits to come. Thus if the animal spirits are dimmed and the spontaneous optimism falters, leaving us to depend on nothing but a mathematical expectation, enterprise will fade and die—though fears of loss may have a basis no more reasonable than hopes of profit had before.45

Finally, he writes that “human decisions affecting the future, whether personal or political or economic, cannot depend on strict mathematical expectation, since the basis for making such calculations does not exist; and…it is our innate urge to activity which makes the wheels go round, our rational selves choosing between the alternatives as best we are able, calculating where we can, but often falling back for our motive on whim or sentiment or chance.”46 As insightful as these words are, we should also remember that they were written by the man on whom modern policymakers are relying to revive the global economy. Policymakers need to understand the entirety of Keynes’ message, not just the parts that they want to hear in a quest for politically expedient solutions to intractable economic problems.

Perhaps Keynes’ most significant insight into human behavior involves what he termed the “paradox of thrift,” the phenomenon that is a version of the “fallacy of composition” discussed earlier. Keynes did not originate this phenomenon; it appears to date back to the 1714 allegorical poem “The Fable of the Bees,” which Keynes quotes from rather extensively in Chapter 23 of The General Theory (who says there is no place for literature in economics—even mediocre literature?). This phenomenon turns on its head all concepts of rational behavior. It also renders most market theories useless in practice. The paradox of thrift holds that if too many people seek to save rather than spend money at one time, the economy will be starved of investment and consumption and economic growth will suffer. The paradox comes from the fact that saving rather than spending is believed to be a constructive activity, yet it leads to economic harm when engaged in by too many people at the same time. This is also true with respect to investment activity. When market conditions lead too many investors to sell at the same time, markets tends to fall rapidly and in some cases collapse. Individual selling decisions may well be rational and designed to protect capital, but when too many investors make such decisions at the same time it leads to massive market losses. Few if any of the classic investment theories such as Harry Markowitz’s modern portfolio theory or William Sharpe’s capital asset pricing model or the Black-Scholes model effectively capture this reality (or other discontinuities, which are admittedly difficult to capture in mathematical language). Moreover, mass selling has the psychological effect of causing panic and leading to further selling, another phenomenon for which the classic investment theories fail to account.

Throughout The General Theory, Keynes stresses the importance of human expectations in economics. In fact, he writes that “the part played by expectations in economic analysis” was one of three “perplexities” that most impeded the writing of his great book.47 For Keynes, expectations about the future are everything. “During a boom,” he writes, “the popular estimation of the magnitude of both these risks, both borrower’s risk and lender’s risk, is apt to become unusually and imprudently low.”48 Human beings tend to believe that the current state of affairs will continue, although their belief is not based on anything to which they can point. “In abnormal times in particular, when the hypothesis of an indefinite continuance of the existing state of affairs is less plausible than usual even though there are no express grounds to anticipate a definite change, the market will be subject to waves of optimistic and pessimistic sentiment, which are unreasoning and yet in a sense legitimate where no solid basis exists for a reasonable calculation.”49 This leads to the uncomfortable reality that whatever the models purport to tell us, markets tend to seize up when large numbers of investors decide to sell at the same time because “there is no such thing as liquidity of investment for the community as a whole.”50

One dramatic example of this phenomenon occurred in 1998 when the hedge fund Long Term Capital Management collapsed. Investors suddenly discovered correlations among different asset classes for which their models had failed to account. This was largely due to the fact that these correlations arose from factors such as overlapping ownership of assets by a concentrated group of institutions and hedge funds, the use of exorbitant amounts of leverage by these holders to own these assets, and other factors that even Nobel Prize winning economists failed to grasp (probably because they were Nobel Prize winners!). These factors led investors to simultaneously sell positions that in theory should not have been correlated but in practice became instantly and highly correlated. One of Keynes’ great strengths is that he didn’t allow mathematical formulas to distract him from the human realities of investing. Hence, the famous adage that is attributed to him, “The market can stay irrational longer than you can stay solvent.” In a world heading ever deeper into insolvency, such words should ring in our ears.

Hyman Minsky

The 2008 financial crisis did a great deal to revive the reputation of Hyman Minsky. The revival was long overdue. Minsky remains a grossly underappreciated thinker, but he understood and acknowledged the importance of those who preceded him. Minsky rightly considered Keynes’ The General Theory to be one of the most important works of modern thought: “[i]f Keynes, along with Marx, Darwin, Freud, and Einstein, belongs in the pantheon of seminal thinkers who triggered modern intellectual revolutions, it is because of the contribution to economics, both as a science and as a relevant guide to public policy, that is contained in his General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money.”51 Minsky’s work is based on his interpretation of Keynes, and it is difficult to read one today without reading the other.

Minsky is known for his “financial-instability hypothesis,” which argues that stable economies sow the seeds of their own demise. Minsky traces this idea back to Keynes’ thinking in The General Theory. Minsky explains that “implicit in [Keynes’] analysis is a view that a capitalist economy is fundamentally flawed.” He continues:

This flaw exists because the financial system necessary for capitalist vitality and vigor—which translates entrepreneurial animal spirits into effective demand for investment—contains the potential for runaway expansion, powered by an investment boom. This runaway expansion is brought to a halt because accumulated financial changes render the financial system fragile, so that not unusual changes can trigger serious financial difficulties. Because Keynes arrived at his views on how a capitalist economy operates by examining problems of decision-making under conditions of intractable uncertainty, in his system, stability, even if it is the result of policy, is destabilizing. Even if policy succeeds in eliminating the waste of great depressions, the fundamental financial attributes of capitalism mean that periodic difficulties in constraining and then sustaining demand will ensue.52

Minsky traced his “financial-instability hypothesis” to Keynes, but there is an even deeper connection that links these two men’s thinking. Keynes’ focus on the importance of human expectations in the face of uncertainty strongly influenced Minsky’s view of how economic actors react to conditions of financial stability.

Implicit in Minsky’s “financial-instability hypothesis” is the assumption that economic actors conduct themselves based on how they feel about their economic environment. When they experience a stable environment, they are emboldened to take risk; when they experience instability and hardship, they tend to act more conservatively. These are primarily psychological reactions to their experiences, an exercise of their “animal spirits” as Keynes described them. These two great economists understood that economic behavior was human behavior, and, as such, was influenced by the forces that govern human beings—feelings and emotion. This relates their work back to Adam Smith, who believed that human beings acted in a certain manner in order to gain the approval of other people. Acting in a manner that gained other peoples’ approval, Smith believed, would reinforce certain types of behavior that were conducive to the development of a fair and just society. The essentially social and psychological nature of all economic behavior then calls us back to Marx’s criticism of capitalism. Marx believed that capitalism would fail because it insufficiently acknowledged the social and human components of labor and instead reduced human relations through the process of fetishism to relationships between things in the form of money. These four thinkers believed that human relationships and emotions lie at the heart of all capitalist processes. As we have learned often enough over the past two decades, any system that fails to adequately account for the human element that lies at the heart of all economic activity is prone to instability and potential failure.

Hyman Minsky was largely unknown outside the world of economic professionals until the financial crisis, although some observers such as PIMCO’s Paul McCulley, The Credit Bubble Bulletin’s Doug Noland, GMO LLC’s Jeremy Grantham, and I were writing about him for several years before his work came all too vividly to life in the summer of 2007.53 Today everybody is a Minsky disciple—or should be. Those who were familiar with Minsky’s work before the crisis were in the best position to predict the credit cataclysm that occurred. Minsky should now take his place next to John Maynard Keynes as one of the twentieth century’s most important economic thinkers. Like those in the pantheon he joins, his contributions were inspired by his keen insights into noneconomic areas of thought such as human psychology.

The “financial-instability hypothesis” can be summarized as follows: The better things get, the better they are expected to continue to be. Human beings tend to extrapolate current conditions indefinitely into the future. Based on the assumption that positive economic conditions will continue, people let their guards down with respect to risk, which leads them to take more of it. As each individual takes more risk, the overall riskiness of the system increases. This is not an insight into economics; it is an insight into human behavior. Minsky did not require a degree in mathematics or physics to come up with his “financial-instability hypothesis”—what he possessed was keen insight into human nature and human psychology.

Minsky expounded on his theory at greatest length in his seminal work, Stabilizing an Unstable Economy (1986). Minsky divided the process of risk absorption into three phases. In the first phase, which he called “hedge finance,” economic actors expect cash flows from their business operations to be sufficient to meet their obligations now and in the future. In the second phase, termed “speculative finance,” economic actors do not expect cash flows from operations to be sufficient to meet all of their cash payment obligations, particularly their short-term obligations. In this phase, actors must roll over existing debt in order to remain solvent. The third phase, which was given the colorful and somewhat controversial name of “Ponzi finance,” involves a situation in which economic actors know that they will not be able to meet their cash obligations through operations and will have to borrow to meet them. In this phase, additional debt must be raised in order to retain solvency.54 Ponzi finance is the dominant characteristic of the global economy today. It is a decidedly unhealthy state of affairs.

The stability of an economy is determined by the mix of these three types of financing structures within it. Hedge finance structures are subject to the risk that business operations will not generate sufficient cash flows to meet future obligations. Speculative and Ponzi finance structures are not only subject to that risk but are vulnerable to a much more significant risk that is outside the control of individual businessmen—the risk that financial markets will become inhospitable and render it difficult to roll over existing debt or raise additional debt to meet future obligations. As Minsky writes, “[s]peculative and Ponzi units must issue debt in order to meet payments and commitments. This means that they must always meet the market. Furthermore, they are vulnerable to any disruption, in the form of transitory unfavorable financing terms, that may occur in financial markets.”55 For this reason, speculative and Ponzi finance structures are far riskier than hedge finance structures, and an economy whose composition is weighted more toward Ponzi financing rather than hedge financing is prone to instability.

Large Western economies became Ponzi economies by the mid-1990s. By the mid-2000s, conditions were so Ponzi-like that it was only a question of “when,” not “if” the system would succumb to internal instability. From homebuyers who borrowed more than their homes were worth based on the belief that home prices would continue rising, to private equity firms that purchased companies at exorbitant prices using debt structures that enabled them to pay interest in additional debt rather than cash, the entire financial system was engaged in one massive Ponzi scheme in the sense that Hyman Minsky used the term. This does not mean that such financing schemes were fraudulent or illegal (although in the case of the mortgage market many reportedly were). It does mean, however, that in most cases they were imprudently or even recklessly constructed.

Minsky’s use of the term Ponzi should not be glossed over. Minsky responded to harsh criticism of his use of the term in a long footnote to his seminal article titled, “The financial-instability hypothesis” (1982): “[t]he type of financial relations that I label Ponzi finance is a quite general and not necessarily fraudulent characteristic of a capitalist financial structure. Financial relations the validation of which depends on the selling out of positions are a normal functioning part of the capitalist process. Furthermore, every ‘bubble’ or stock-market speculation in which profitability depends on the timing of entry and exit is of the nature of a ‘Ponzi scheme.’”56 Recent commentators who have brought Minsky’s work back to the prominence that it deserves have devoted little attention to Minsky’s terminology, but it deserves further emphasis than it has received.

Minsky’s use of the term “Ponzi” in describing the type of financial structure that grew predominant in the late twentieth and early twenty-first century should not be considered disingenuous. Ponzi is not a morally neutral word. It refers to Charles Ponzi, an infamous swindler who, for a short period in 1920, employed the technique of using money raised from later investors to repay earlier investors. He was not the first and certainly not the last crook to employ such a scheme, but his name stuck to it (although Bernie Madoff has offered himself as an alternative, with the new term “being Madoff’d” starting to sneak into modern vernacular). Minsky was making a point in using such a value-laden term, and despite his seemingly innocent disclaimer about his intent, there can be no question of his disapproval:

However, the label attached to the financing relations I identify as Ponzi is not important. What is important is whether or not such structures exist and what effect such financing has on system behavior. In particular, if Ponzi financing exists, if the extent of Ponzi financing determines the domain of instability of the economy, and if Ponzi financing is a normal adjunct of investment production, then there are normally functioning endogenous factors that make for significant instabilities.57

Minsky’s insight about Ponzi structures is of crucial importance in understanding modern capitalism. Ponzi finance is highly unstable; it is vulnerable not only to changes in conditions of borrowers, but to deterioration in market conditions. Ponzi finance is closely associated with financial instability. Describing such a state of affairs with a term associated with a swindler should not be understood as value neutral; it is a way of suggesting that such financing structures are irresponsible and immoral, even if they are not illegal. The fact that they lead to financial instability that causes social unrest, higher unemployment, a widening of the gap between rich and poor, and other adverse consequences suggests that such financing structures should be viewed as reckless and socially damaging. In his own deadpan way, this is what Minsky was trying to tell us.

Government policies that permit Ponzi finance to flourish end up imposing an enormous burden on society. This is why an increasing number of economists take issue with former Federal Reserve Chairman Alan Greenspan’s view that a central bank should not take action with respect to a sharp increase in asset prices. In fact, Minsky teaches that it is not rising asset prices per se that should trigger countercyclical policy by central banks so much as the reasons behind the rise. If Ponzi finance structures are responsible for pushing prices higher, central banks should begin tightening policy and taking other steps to counter the process. Failing to take any action in the face of sharply rising asset prices that were being fed by an orgy of leverage in the form of Ponzi finance turned out to be a catastrophic error on Greenspan’s part during his term, a mistake that was repeated by his successor Ben Bernanke during the first two years of his term and, after being interrupted by the financial crisis, were again perpetuated by the Janet Yellen-led Federal Reserve and other major central banks in the post-crisis years. Minsky’s “financial-instability hypothesis” also renders highly dubious concepts such as “the great moderation” that Bernanke endorsed in advocating that the economy had reached a new era of stability in the mid-2000s. Bernanke promulgated this view in a widely noted speech in 2004 and again in a 2006 speech and clung to it until 2007. A careful reading of Minsky, however, would have led Bernanke to reach just the opposite conclusion—that benign economic conditions would lead, not to further stability, but to instability. This turned out to be a profound intellectual error as it led the Federal Reserve to follow a lax monetary policy for far too long.

It is one thing when manufacturing firms collapse under the weight of their debts and other obligations; their balance sheets can be restructured and their assets sold or liquidated in the process Joseph Schumpeter described as “creative destruction.” The presumption is that more productive businesses will take their place in the economy. But when financial firms run into trouble because they cannot pay their debts, a larger societal interest is harmed because of the public utility function that financial institutions play in the economy. This is particularly true in regulated industries where the government has provided an explicit or implicit guarantee. The collapse of a financial firm leads to deflationary debt destruction as capital is wiped out. This leads to a loss of confidence among economic actors that leads to the death of capital. When that occurs, governments must act through their central banks and fulfill their functions as lenders of last resort. In 2008, conditions became so desperate that the world saw its central banks and governments perform this function in previously unimagined ways.

Lessons on Capital from the Masters

Smith, Marx, Keynes, and Minsky are deserving of a much more thorough examination than they have received here. The point of this discussion of their work is to draw out some common insights that these intellectual giants offer with respect to capital and capitalist processes. First, all of them consider capital and capitalism to be highly unstable phenomena that are subject to the emotions of economic actors in the marketplace. This renders markets themselves highly unstable and subject to cycles of boom and bust. Second, the unavoidable conclusion that reading these men’s work leads to is that understanding capital, capitalism, and markets requires a deep understanding of human nature, in particular the irrational and emotional side of human nature. Mathematical understanding is of limited utility when it comes to navigating financial markets because the forces that drive these markets are not mathematical or rational in nature. Third, these four thinkers believe that capitalist processes bear within themselves the seeds of their own instability and potential destruction. The innate nature of capital and capitalism involves contradictions and conflicts that lead to instability. Further, mathematical and rational thinking often leads to instability and irrational outcomes. From a practical standpoint, this means that every bull market sows the seeds of its own demise, a lesson investors forget at their own peril.

Reading these seminal thinkers then raises the question about what one should think about the fact that so much of modern finance theory and market dogma is guided by belief in concepts such as efficient markets, quantitative finance, and other rational constructs that are repeatedly contradicted by the real world experience of investors. Why do investors ignore not only the best that has been thought about markets but their own experiences, and as a result repeatedly subject themselves to catastrophic losses? The answer lies in the fact that investors, who also happen to be human beings, cannot escape their essential nature. Emotion is such a powerful phenomenon precisely because it trumps reason. Men are made to believe that the future will resemble the past, and in some respects it does. But they tend to be extremely selective about which parts of the past they choose to remember.

As with so many complex systems, markets discovered in 2007 and 2008 that the tools designed to reduce risk introduced new risks that hadn’t been contemplated before. Even worse, these risks were hidden by the complex and opaque nature of the new financial instruments that were sold as risk management tools. These products contained within them the seeds of their own demise because they were not in fact new creations but just another form of capital and subject to the same laws that always govern capital. If we are to contain the madness of crowds, we need to help them understand what is driving them insane. In uncovering the answer to this question, we learn that the fault lies not in the stars but in ourselves. For while every individual rationally pursues economic goals that he believes will enrich him or her, the aggregation of those individual desires tends to lead to instability. It is no accident, therefore, that each of the four thinkers discussed in this chapter emphasizes the important role played in the markets by the “fallacy of composition.” Cycles of boom and bust will remain with us as long as we remain human. Try as we might to remove the human element from economics, the dismal science remains in its essence trapped by who we are.

Notes

..................Content has been hidden....................

You can't read the all page of ebook, please click here login for view all page.
Reset